Skiplinks

  • Tekst
  • Verantwoording en downloads
  • Doorverwijzing en noten
Logo DBNL Ga naar de homepage
Logo DBNL

Hoofdmenu

  • Literatuur & taal
    • Auteurs
    • Beschikbare titels
    • Literatuur
    • Taalkunde
    • Collectie Limburg
    • Collectie Friesland
    • Collectie Suriname
    • Collectie Zuid-Afrika
  • Selecties
    • Collectie jeugdliteratuur
    • Basisbibliotheek
    • Tijdschriften/jaarboeken
    • Naslagwerken
    • Collectie e-books
    • Collectie publiek domein
    • Calendarium
    • Atlas
  • Periode
    • Middeleeuwen
    • Periode 1550-1700
    • Achttiende eeuw
    • Negentiende eeuw
    • Twintigste eeuw
    • Eenentwintigste eeuw
A New Critique of Theoretical Thought. Deel 2. The General Theory of the Modal Spheres (1969)

Informatie terzijde

Titelpagina van A New Critique of Theoretical Thought. Deel 2. The General Theory of the Modal Spheres
Afbeelding van A New Critique of Theoretical Thought. Deel 2. The General Theory of the Modal SpheresToon afbeelding van titelpagina van A New Critique of Theoretical Thought. Deel 2. The General Theory of the Modal Spheres

  • Verantwoording
  • Inhoudsopgave

Downloads

PDF van tekst (3.07 MB)

Scans (34.95 MB)

XML (1.61 MB)

tekstbestand






Vertalers

H. de Jongste

David H. Freeman



Genre

non-fictie

Subgenre

non-fictie/filosofie-ethiek
vertaling: Nederlands / Engels


In samenwerking met:

(opent in nieuw venster)

© zie Auteursrecht en gebruiksvoorwaarden.

A New Critique of Theoretical Thought. Deel 2. The General Theory of the Modal Spheres

(1969)–H. Dooyeweerd–rechtenstatus Auteursrechtelijk beschermd

Vorige Volgende
[pagina 491]
[p. 491]

Chapter III
The problem regarding the possibility of the synthesis of meaning in the so-called critical transcendental philosophy of Kant.

§ 1 - The dogmatic character of the crypto-religious attitude in critical epistemology.

It should now be clear that a truly critical epistemology is dependent on the self-reflection on the cosmonomic Idea from which the thinkers starts.

In the problem of the inter-modal synthesis of meaning the very possibility of theoretical thought is at issue. Every epistemology that supposes it can find its Archimedean point in transcendental thought and pose the epistemological problem apart from a transcendental cosmonomic Idea, is ‘dogmatism’ in the objectionable sense of the word.

Such a theory may later on raise the problem of the possibility of the theoretical synthesis. But in its functionalistic attitude it takes no account of the possibility of the primary theoretic synthesis absolutized in its cosmonomic Idea, without which the isolation of the logical or the psychical functions would not be possible.

It is the dogmatic rejection of religious self-reflection that is typical of this doctrinair attitude of theoretical thoughtGa naar voetnoot1. It refuses to carry thought in the transcendental direction to its utmost limits; not, because of purely theoretical motives, as it presumes, but precisely on account of its essentially religious postulate regarding the absolute self-sufficiency of the ‘Ver-

[pagina 492]
[p. 492]

nunft’ which it wants to save at all costs. And this attitude of thought is forced on us, in the tyranny of every theoretical dogmatism, as the only scientific one.

No one should now attempt to maintain this dogmatism with the old argument that philosophy qua talis cannot exceed the theoretical field.

Already in the Prolegomena it has been sufficiently explained that we do not wish to contradict this thesis for a moment. In truly critical-transcendental thought, however, the philosopher should at least theoretically take account of the transcendent and the transcendental conditions without which philosophic thought is impossible. In this respect the cosmonomic Idea as a theoretical Idea in no way exceeds the limits of philosophy, though we know that this Idea itself is always religiously determined. It is much rather the postulate of the self-sufficiency of theoretical thought that cannot be epistemologically accounted for. It has not been theoretically thought out in the transcendental direction of time and it forces its religious a priori on us in the disguise of a ‘pure theory’.

If with Theodor Litt one speaks of a lack of ‘logical integrity’Ga naar voetnoot1, this epithet would sooner fit such a crypto-religious attitude of thought than the philosophy of the cosmonomic Idea which tears off its mask.

The reason why in this context we do not discuss the doctrine of the transcendental Ideas of the Kritik der reinen Vernunft and base our exposition for the present on the second edition only.

We shall demonstrate in some detail that epistemology could not but get involved in an impasse on the immanence-standpoint. As an example we take Kant's epistemology, on whose fundamental theses the so-called critical, transcendental-idealistic philosophy is still founded. For the present our exposition will be based only on the second edition of the Kritik der reinen Vernunft. By so doing I need not yet fear the contradiction which might be inspired by Heidegger's interpretation of Kant's Kritik der reinen Vernunft in its first edition. In the present context our sole purpose is to characterize the ‘critical method’ as such in its failure with regard to the central problem of all epistemology.

[pagina 493]
[p. 493]

Heidegger is of opinion that Kant's Kritik der reinen Vernunft has got nothing to do with epistemology, at least in its original conception, as it is found in the first edition. Its subject is supposed to be the possibility of an ontology. I think this hypothesis untenable, and intend to submit it to a special investigation later on. For the present I leave this recent controversy alone. Even if Heidegger's interpretation of Kant's original meaning should be correct, nobody can reasonably raise objections to my discussing the second edition as the basic work for the critical method in epistemology. This procedure is safeguarded by the fact that Heidegger himself acknowledges his peculiar interpretation to be inapplicable to the second edition.

Kant's doctrine of Ideas, in which the transcendental direction in philosophic thought begins to manifest itself, is intentionally omitted here, since it has been discussed in an earlier context. This is no distortion of Kant's critique of knowledge.

In the first place, I have definitely shown that Kant's epistemology can be understood only on the basis of his Idea of human personality as the autonomous ‘homo noumenon’. And secondly, I have demonstrated that his doctrine of Ideas is really determined by his practical a priori ‘faith in reason’. These two points belong to the exposition of Kant's cosmonomic Idea, discussed in the second part of the first volume.

For the posing and the solution of the problem regarding the cognitive synthesis Kant cannot appeal to his doctrine of Ideas. This is caused by the very nature of his dualistic cosmonomic Idea.

In the transcendental dialectic the theoretical Ideas make their first appearance. And this dialectic is only considered after a complete discussion of the cognitive synthesis and of the cogito, the supposed Archimedean point of Kant's epistemology. Thus Kant himself suggests that his critique of knowledge has been composed apart from any religious attitude and is quite unprejudiced, as the product of ‘pure theoretical reflection’Ga naar voetnoot1.

[pagina 494]
[p. 494]

And this suggestion was accepted by the whole of critical thought in the struggle against speculative metaphysics. It was raised as a bulwark to bar religious prejudices and ‘Weltanschauung’ from the domain of epistemology.

Kant's theory will prove to result in a stalemate and involve itself in intrinsic self-contradiction.

§ 2 - Kant's doctrine of the synthesis and of the unity of our self-consciousness.

In the first place it will be clear that the mere isolation of the Transcendental Aesthetic and the Transcendental Logic is based on a fundamental misconception of the epistemological problem.

Kant did not realize that the doctrine of the sensory material of experience, in its primitive reception in the ‘transcendental forms of intuition of space and time’, pre-supposes the theoretical analysis and inter-modal synthesis of meaning.

His thesis is that the ‘datum’ in the ‘Gegenstand’ is nothing but the chaotic sensory ‘Empfindungen’Ga naar voetnoot1.

He adopted this thesis from Hume's psychologism uncritically, without being aware of its self-refuting character. How can the datum be the result of an analytical ἐποχή, the product of theoretical isolation? Kant writes: ‘In the transcendental aesthetics accordingly, we shall first isolate sensibility, separating from it all that the understanding adds to it by means of its concepts so that nothing may be left but empirical intuition’Ga naar voetnoot2.

Already at this point, and also in the ‘transcendental logic’ Kant ought to have raised the problem regarding the possibility of the theoretical antithesis and the inter-modal synthesis of meaning.

It is typical of his dogmatic attitude with respect to theoretical

[pagina 495]
[p. 495]

thought as such that he did not sense an epistemological problem connected with the isolation of the sensory aspect of experience.

Instead he thinks that after the theoretical isolating process nothing remains but a given ‘non-conceptual’ sensory intuition, apart from any connection with the logical aspect of thought. Consequently Kant is not aware of the antinomy implied in the attempt at the theoretical isolation of a ‘pure’ sensibility. Not before his Transcendental Doctrine of the Faculty of Judgment does he raise the problem, as to how to apply the isolated ‘categories of thought’ to the sensory ‘matter’ of experience.

But the primordial epistemological problem regarding the antithetical ‘Gegenstand-relation’ as such and the transcendental conditions of the possibility of a theoretic abstraction of the sensory and the logical aspects of experience, is not even taken into consideration. Kant was not aware of the cosmic temporal meaning-coherence between the modal aspects. If so, he would have seen that the theoretical abstraction of the sensory (psychical) function of experience remains bound to the modal structure of the latter. This structure expresses the inner meaning-coherence with the logical and all the other aspects. Therefore he would have realized that a pure sensibility is a contradiction in terminis, since its very nature is to imply the analogies of the other modalities of meaning.

The influence of the metaphysical substance-concept upon Kant's epistemology.

It deserves special attention that in his transcendental logic Kant accepts an a priori reference of the categories to the sensory aspect of experience, whereas he does not acknowledge an a priori appeal of the latter to the categories.

In § 13 of the second chapter of the Transcendental Analytic, entitled Von den Prinzipien einer transszendentalen Deduktion überhaupt. Kant emphatically remarks: ‘for phenomena can certainly be given in the sensory intuition independently of functions of the understanding’Ga naar voetnoot1. It is true that in § 16 (in which

[pagina 496]
[p. 496]

the Original Synthetic Unity of Apperception is discussed) it is said that ‘all the manifold of the sensory intuition is necessarily related to the “I think” in the same subject in which this manifold is found.’ But this reference does not include an appeal to the logical categories of thought as appears from the preceding quotation.

The reason is that Kant's epistemology is in many respects influenced by the metaphysical concept of the ‘thing in itself’ (substance).

We remember that in Aristotelian metaphysics the ‘substance’ (οὐσία ) was supposed to be quite independent of human thought. The latter, on the contrary, was supposed to be intrinsically related to the substances. This conception has been accepted by critical realism in contemporary philosophy. Although Kant's critique of pure reason resulted in a transcendental idealism, he was of opinion that the ‘sensory matter’ of experience originates in a mysterious affection of our senses by the unknowable ‘thing in itself’. So it is quite understandable that he did not accept an intrinsic relation of the sensory function of experience to the transcendental forms of logical thought, but only an a priori relation of the latter to the former, to ‘Gegenstände der (sinnlichen) Anschauung’. This metaphysical view is bound up with his conception of the purely receptive rôle of the ‘Sinnlichkeit’ and the active and free spontaneity of the understanding. In a deeper sense this conception was determined by the dialectical Humanistic basic motive of nature and freedom. Kant did not know the modal structure of the logical aspect and its temporal meaning-coherence with the other aspects of experience. Consequently his thesis about the a priori reference of the categories to objects of sensory intuition required another foundation. This foundation was supposed to be provided in the famous chapter of the Transcendental Logic concerning the Transcendental Deduction of the Pure Concepts of the Understanding (the categories). The demonstrative power of this chapter stands and falls with its presuppositions, which are not critical at all, but rather prescribed by the hidden starting-point of Kant's epistemology.

Kant's first discussion of the problem of synthesis. His lack of distinction between the logical synthesis and the inter-modal synthesis.

The basis of the whole argument is to be found in his conception of the synthesis as ‘the combination of a manifold as

[pagina 497]
[p. 497]

such’ and its transcendental logical unity, guaranteed by the original synthetical unity of apperception. In advance of all investigation Kant proclaims that this synthesis is an actus of the spontaneity of the understanding (conceived of in the theoretical abstraction of a ‘pure’ logical function). The only argument adduced for this thesis is that ‘the synthesis of a manifold as such’ cannot be ascribed to the senses. The latter are only receptive, and even the forms of sensory intuition are nothing but the way in which the subject is affected by the things in themselves.

In the preceding chapter (§ 10) containing an introductory discussion of the categories, Kant distinguishes synthesis as such from the function to conceive it in a conceptual form. The former is called the mere result of the power of imagination (Einbildungskraft), ‘a blind, though indispensable function of the soul, without which we would have no knowledge at all, and of which we are nevertheless scarcely ever conscious’. The function of conceiving the synthesis of imagination in a conceptual form is exclusively attributed to the understanding, which by this function provides us with knowledge properly so-called. This is indeed a dark point in Kant's argument which we shall discuss in detail later on. For the present we are entitled to eliminate it because it will appear from the sequel that it is of no consequence for Kant's epistemological conception of synthesis.

Kant himself emphatically states that all combination, no matter whether we are aware of it or not, is an act of the understandingGa naar voetnoot1.

This is to say that even the unconscious imagination can execute the synthesis only by means of the logical function of the understanding.

Since the theoretical abstraction of the sensory and the logical functions of experience does not imply an epistemological problem for Kant, this line of thought must result in the thesis that theoretical synthesis is the pre-requisite of all analysis:

‘The reader will easily enough perceive that this act’ (viz. the transcendental synthesis) ‘must be originally one and the same and of equal validity for every synthesis, and that its dissolution, viz. analysis, which appears to be its opposite, must, nevertheless, always pre-suppose it; for where the understanding has not previously combined, it cannot dissolve or analyse, since only as having been combined by the understanding can any-

[pagina 498]
[p. 498]

thing that allows of analysis be given to the faculty of representation’Ga naar voetnoot1.

Kant does not recognize the cosmic systasis of meaning as it is determined and arranged by the cosmic temporal order, and in which the analytical function itself can only function. Theoretical thought has to take over the task of the cosmic law-giver. And so Kant cannot understand that logical synthesis itself is under the law of the analytical meaning and can never be the pre-requisite of the analytical. The modal meaning of the law-spheres is erased by the absolutizing of the theoretical logical function. And this is another reason why the problem of the inter-modal synthesis of meaning in theoretical knowledge must remain hidden from Kant. He does not distinguish the latter from the functional logical synthesis. According to him all synthesis, no matter whether it is a combination of the manifold of sensory intuition or of a logical manifold of concepts, is a logical act of the understandingGa naar voetnoot2.

The lack of genuinely transcendental reflection culminates in Kant's ‘Transcendental Logic’ in the logicizing of the cosmic and cosmological self-consciousness.

His argument starts from the concept of combination which in addition to those of the manifold and of synthesis also pre-supposes that of unity. Kant has penetrated to the insight that the categories of thought as conceptual forms of synthesis pre-suppose the basic unity of self-consciousness:

‘We must, therefore, look still higher for this unity (as qualitative)Ga naar voetnoot3 namely in that which contains the ground of the unity of diverse concepts in judgments; the ground, consequently, of the possibility of the understanding, even in regard to its logical employment’Ga naar voetnoot4. (Italics are mine).

[pagina 499]
[p. 499]

If Kant had not started from the dogma concerning the autonomy of theoretical thought, he might have acknowledged the necessary transcendence of self-consciousness (operating in theoretical thought) above the logical function. Now he has barred the way to this transcendental insight. The theoretically abstracted logical and sensory functions are assumed to be the only sources of our knowledge. The transcendental unity of self-consciousness cannot be found in sensibility: so it must be of a logical nature after all. Kant identifies it with the cogito as the form of the representation ‘I think’. He explicitly calls the fundamental law of the necessary unity of apperception (i.e. the transcendental unity of self-consciousness) an ‘analytical proposition’.

The transcendental unity of self-consciousness is the concept of the ‘cogito’ that must be capable of accompanying all my different theoretical concepts, if they are to be my own concepts. It is thus made the mere transcendental logical pre-requisite for all theoretical categories of thought. In an epistemological sense, the selfhood is merged into the primary logical unity of thought:

‘for the sole reason that I can comprehend the manifold of the representations in one consciousness, do I call them my representations, for otherwise I should have as many-coloured and diverse a self as I have representations of which I am conscious.
Synthetical unity of the manifold in intuitions as givenGa naar voetnoot1 a priori, is therefore the ground of the identity of apperception itself which is a priori antecendent to all my determinate thought. Combination, however, is not found in the objects themselves; it cannot be derived from them through perception and then taken up into the understanding. On the contrary, it is a function of the understanding alone, which itself is no more than the faculty of combining a priori and of bringing the manifold of given representations under the unity of apperception. This principle is the highest in all human knowledge’Ga naar voetnoot2.
[pagina 500]
[p. 500]

The internal antinomy in Kant's conception of the transcendental unity of self-consciousness.

The whole internal antinomy of the so-called critical transcendental epistemology is implied in nuce in this view of the cognitive selfhood as merely a logical form of the unity of consciousness. The deeper identity experienced in our self-consciousness is of a transfunctional and super-temporal character. It is knowing oneself to be one and the same in and beyond all cosmic temporal functions and knowing one's functions as one's own. If the thinking I-ness would be logical-functional, it would have to resist all non-logical aspects of reality, the psychical included, as not my own, not belonging to my selfhood. It would have to do so on the ground of the principium contradictionis. This would also cancel the possibility of a meaning-synthesis between the logical function of thought and Kant's sensory experiential material. In other words, Kant's critique of knowledge destroys itself by setting our cognitive functions apart and making them independent, and by identifying cognitive selfhood with the primary logical unity of the activity of thoughtGa naar voetnoot1. It is true, Kant qualified the original unity of apperception in the ‘pure self-consciousness’ explicitly as a synthetical unity (in the sense of a form or law-conformity determining all experience). He considered it as the original a priori relatedness of a multiplicity (in intuition) to the cogito, the ‘I think’, in the same subject in which this multiplicity is found.

It is true also that Kant founds the purely analytical ‘unity of apperception’ - of which he assumes that it coalesces with

[pagina 501]
[p. 501]

the representation (i.e. the concept) of the identity of consciousness in a multiplicity of given representations - in the synthetical unity of apperceptionGa naar voetnoot1. But all this does not concern the possibility of inter-modal meaning-synthesis in the transcendental unity of self-consciousness. Kant writes: ‘the manifold representations given in an intuition would not all of them be my representations if they did not all belong to one self-consciousness’Ga naar voetnoot2. But if this self-consciousness is only the final logical unity of the activity of thought, it remains in an antithetical position towards sensibility, because of the theoretical isolation in which Kant conceives of it. Then the sensory representations cannot possibly be related to self-consciousness. In Kant's functionalistic critique of knowledge the religious transcendence of the selfhood, the cosmic interlacement of the modal functions in time, and the theoretical intuition cannot possibly play a partGa naar voetnoot3.

The transcendental unity of apperception in Kant remains essentially a supposed ultimate formal unity of the logical function of thought.

The following quotations may be additional evidence for this statement:

‘in the transcendental synthesis of the manifold of representations in general, and also in the original synthetic unity of

[pagina 502]
[p. 502]

apperception I am conscious of myself, not as I appear to myself, but only of the fact that I am. This representation is a thought, not an intuition’Ga naar voetnoot1. A little further on we read: ‘I exist as an intelligence which is conscious solely of its power of combination’Ga naar voetnoot2 etc., and Kant explicitly calls the objective unity of apperception ‘the logical form of all judgments’Ga naar voetnoot3, whereas repeatedly he emphasizes that thought in itself is nothing but ‘the logical function’Ga naar voetnoot4.

Summary of our criticism of Kant's conception of the transcendental unity of self-consciousness.

We can sum up the internal contradiction in Kant's conception of ‘the transcendental unity of apperception’ as follows:

The synthesis of meaning pre-supposes a temporal coherence of meaning in the modal diversity, as well as the transcendent unity above the modal diversity. Kant assumes a final logical unity of thinking above logical multiplicityGa naar voetnoot5. To this unity all multiplicity both in thought and in intuition is supposedly related. Logical unity above logical multiplicity, however, cannot possibly exist, because the modal meaning of the logical only contains logical unity in logical multiplicityGa naar voetnoot6. In Kant's epistemology the super-logical unity of self-consciousness is precluded a priori by his dualistic cosmonomic Idea in which this epistemology is founded. The result is that Kant's logicizing of the transcendental unity of self-consciousness cancels itself in internal antinomy.

[pagina 503]
[p. 503]

The selfhood, as the unity above the diversity of meaning, can never be grasped in a concept, but only intended in a transcendental Idea. In Kant's transcendental logic the I-ness has become a formal concept, viz. the logical unity above logical multiplicity. This is nothing but a transposition of the metaphysical concept of the ‘soul’ as a ‘simple substance’ into the modal meaning of the logical aspect, where this concept is even more self-contradictory.

§ 3 - The problem of the inter-modal synthesis of meaning in Kant's so-called transcendental logic.

Kant speaks of the transcendental unity of self-consciousness in order to express that it is the pre-requisite of all a priori cognition. Self-consciousness is the Archimedean point in Kant's epistemology. He conceives it as the transcendental logical condition of knowledge determining everything else. But we saw that he had not even touched upon the primordial fundamental problems of epistemology in his doctrine of the transcendental unity of apperception (i.e. the logical form of self-consciousness).

This raises the inevitable question: What did he really mean by his distinction between transcendental and formal logic, fundamental to his entire critique of knowledge?

Although in critical philosophy this distinction is considered to be of extraordinary importance, it has not been very clearly definedGa naar voetnoot1. All are agreed that ‘transcendental logic’ is concerned with ‘synthetical’ cognitive thought.

[pagina 504]
[p. 504]

It is not possible to doubt that by ‘transcendental logic’ Kant meant the doctrine of ‘pure understanding’, in contradistinction to the so-called ‘formal logic’ already discussed. By means of the ‘pure understanding’ we think ‘Gegenstände’ absolutely a priori, so that the a priori concepts of the ‘pure understanding’ are related to ‘Gegenstände’. On the other hand general or formal logic is supposed to abstract from all relationships between thought and ‘Gegenstände’ and only to concentrate on the ‘form of thought as such’.

The question, however, as to what cosmological character is attached to the ‘synthesis’ brought about in transcendental thought, and in what cosmological sense we have to take the a priori relatedness of the categories of thought to the ‘Gegenstände’ of cognition, has never been investigated, as far as I know.

In Kant's transcendental categories the problem of the inter-modal synthesis of meaning has not been seen.

A close study of Kant's exposition of the character of the transcendental logic with regard to the ‘pure categories of thought’ will reveal that he especially thinks of the logical function as operative in the categories. In his ‘Lecture on Logic’ (Logikvorlesung) he calls the latter ‘Notionen’ or conceptus dati a prioriGa naar voetnoot1.

As sharply as possible he puts in the foreground that it is the same function which is active in formal analytical and in transcendental synthetical thought.

‘The same function,’ says Kant, ‘which gives unity to the various representations’ (i.e. concepts) ‘in a judgment, also lends unity to the mere synthesis of the different representations in an intuition which is called a pure concept of the understanding.
‘The understanding produces the logical form of a jugdment in concepts by means of analytical unity. And it is the same understanding which by the same operations imparts a transcendental content to its representations by means of the synthetic unity of the manifold in intuition. For this reason they are called pure concepts of the understanding, applying a priori to objects. This is a synthetic function beyond the power of general logic’Ga naar voetnoot2.
[pagina 505]
[p. 505]
And in § 20 of the Transcendental Logic we read: ‘That operation of the understanding, however, by which the manifold of some given representations (be they intuitions or concepts) is brought under one apperception, is the logical function of judgment.’ (Italics are mine). ‘Consequently all of the manifold, in so far as it is given in a single empirical intuition, is determined in relation to one of the logical functions of judgment, by which it is brought into union in one consciousness. Now the categories are nothing else but these same functions’ (Italics are mine) ‘of judgment as far the manifold of a given intuition is determined in relation to them’Ga naar voetnoot1.

In Kant's view ‘synthetical thought’, with its categories applied a priori to ‘Gegenstände’, is thus rooted in the same logical function as formal analytical thought. This is why he orientates the categories to the table of the formal logical judgmentsGa naar voetnoot2.

In Kant's line of argument this orientation is not arbitrary. It is justified in principle because the categories (as to their modal meaning, we would say) are indeed of a logical nature. Consequently, it is confusing to contrast them with the purely logical forms of the theoretical activity of the understanding, as is done by Windelband and in the prevailing view. This would imply that with regard to their formal peculiar character they had a meaning different from the logical. Kant never meant this.

[pagina 506]
[p. 506]

He only distinguished them from all others as synthetic logical concepts a priori applied to possible experience. The synthesis in which the categories themselves are founded was not considered by Kant as an inter-modal but as a purely logical synthesis. The neo-Kantians of the Marburg School who raise objections to Kant's supposed deduction of the categories of thought from the table of logical judgments, by no means wish to detract from the logical origin of the categories. Only those who abandon the elevation of the logos to the (pseudo) Archimedean point of philosophic thought can gain an insight into the real epistemological character of the inter-modal theoretical synthesis of meaning.

So long as the logical is taken to be the origin of all determinateness of meaning, the inter-modal synthesis of meaning as well as the modal meaning-structure drop out of the theoretical view. According to Kant the (theoretical) synthesis of a ‘multiplicity in sensory intuition’ is of a logical functional character, though it doubtless implies a conjunction between two different modal functions of experience. It is even conceived apart from the theoretical intuition of time which only makes the inter-modal synthesis possible. It is ‘a priori related’ to the sensory function of experience, but in Kant's line of thought this relation is completely problematical. Its problematical nature renders it insufficient to accord a more than logical meaning to the categories. And Kant did not intend to do so. In his Kritik der praktischen Vernunft he makes use of the table of the categories quite apart from any sensory experience; and in the first chapter of the Transzendentale Doktrin der Urteilskraft he emphatically states: ‘Indeed a meaning is left to the pure concepts of the understanding also after every sensory condition has been abstracted. But this is only a logical meaning’ (Italics are mine) ‘of the mere unity of the representation to which no “Gegenstand” and consequently no meaning has been given that might produce a concept of the object. So, e.g., “substance”, after all sensory determination of stability has been abstracted, can only mean something that can be thought of as a subject without being a predicate to anything else. I can infer nothing from this representation, because it tells me nothing at all about the determinations of a thing that should be accepted as such a first subject. Consequently, the categories without schemata are only functions of the understanding for concepts, but do not represent an object. They derive the latter sense from

[pagina 507]
[p. 507]

sensibility which realizes the understanding by restricting it at the same time’Ga naar voetnoot1.

And in the 22nd paragraph on Transcendental Logic Kant writes that ‘the categories have their origin in the understanding alone, independently of sensibility’Ga naar voetnoot2,Ga naar voetnoot3.

[pagina 508]
[p. 508]

In this last pronouncement it is especially the part italicized by Kant himself that is important. For it states emphatically that in his own view the category itself implies no inter-modal synthesis of meaning. It is true he never tires of asserting that a category cannot be used for cognizing things in any other way than by applying it to the objects of experienceGa naar voetnoot1. Bu this confirms the statement that it is only the synthesis of the categories with the ‘transcendental form of sensory intuition’ time that can have an inter-functional, inter-modal character in Kant's line of thought.

Criticism of Kant's table of categories.

At this very point, however, Kant's lack of a cosmological foundation for his epistemology is very evident. His prejudice that we can acquire knowledge from two ‘sources’ only has no room for more than one kind of inter-functional synthesis a priori in cognition, viz. that between a logical category and a form of sensory intuition. In addition he could not call this a synthesis since he had bound himself to the prejudice that all synthesis is only a logical function of the understanding.

So Kant could not see that, if his categories were really to be transcendental conditions of mathematical natural scientific knowledge, they must already contain inter-modal syntheses of meaning.

The mathematical categories must combine original mathematical and logical meaning, the dynamical categories must contain original physical meaning in analytical abstractionGa naar voetnoot2, if they are to render mathematics and physics possible.

We have shown that unity, plurality and totality (Kant's categories of quantity) in the logical aspect are entirely distinct from the numerical unit, the numerical manifold, and numerical totality, as well as from the sensory analogies of the latter.

[pagina 509]
[p. 509]

Kant creates endless confusion when he ascribes the origin of number to a schematism of the categories of quantity by which the latter are supposed to assume an a priori sensible image in time as a form of sensory intuition. For lack of insight into the modal structures of meaning he was not aware of the analogical character of his supposed purely logical categories of quantity. His mathematical categories of ‘quality’ (reality, negation, limitation) can have kinematical-mathematical modality only if (as categories of ‘intensive magnitude’) they possess the complicated synthetical structure of meaning analysed in the general theory of the modal spheres.

The categories of quality must then comprise the logically disclosed modality of motion in a synthetical meaning-coherence with the logically disclosed arithmetical and spatial aspect. But Kant ascribes to these categories a logical meaning a priori related to sensory intuition.

He is not aware of the analogical character of the terms reality, negation and limitation in their logical use, and has not analysed their meaning as categories of intensive magnitude. In consequence the fundamental concepts of the kinematical branch of mathematics are misinterpreted as an a priori ‘synthesis of sensation (Empfindung) with the representation of time’, in which sensation is conceived of as ‘content of time’Ga naar voetnoot1. Kant also says that they are a priori determinations of time after rules (viz. the categories of quality), with respect to the content of timeGa naar voetnoot2.

Apart from their a priori reference to ‘time’ Kant's categories of quality, just as his categories of quantity, relation and modality, lose their supposed character as ‘transcendental conditions of experience’. But his conception of time is the weakest point of his epistemology. We have seen that the origin of this conception is doubtless to be traced back to Newton's ‘absolute time’. Apart from its metaphysical interpretation the latter was conceived in a kinematical-mathematical sense, this is to say in the modal meaning of pure uniform motion (tempus quod aequaliter fluit), in its abstraction from the energy-aspect. Kant has only substituted a transcendental-idealistic for a metaphysical interpretation by making time into a pure form of sensory

[pagina 510]
[p. 510]

intuition. He has neither abandoned the kinematical-mathematical sense of Newton's concept of time, nor the absolutization of the kinematical time-aspect. The conception of the latter as a pure form of sensory intuition, in which the subjective impressions of the ‘inner sense’ are supposed to be received, must result in a fundamental confusion. Kant's epistemology has neither room for the modal diversity of the different aspects of time nor for the distinction between its law-side as temporal order and its factual side as duration, nor for the subject-object relation in the experience of time.

The impossibility of a really critical epistemology apart from a cosmological foundation is nowhere more convincingly demonstrated than in Kant's discussion of this most fundamental problem of philosophy.

It is of no avail to say that Kant's conception of time was oriented only to Newton's physics and its mathematical foundations. Even in this restricted sense the problem of time cannot be critically discussed without an insight into its integral cosmological characterGa naar voetnoot1 and the modal diversity of its different aspects. As soon as this state of affairs is lost sight of, every critique of human knowledge lands in a cosmological dogmatism.

Kant's mathematical categories of quantity and quality, as logical functions of the synthesis of a ‘manifold in general’, are related to the same confused idea of time, and by the intermediary of the latter to ‘Gegenstände überhaupt’. It is impossible that these categories which in themselves are nothing but logical forms of judgments, could assume numerical and kinematical-mathematical sense as transcendental determinations of time if the latter is conceived as a pure form of sensory intuition.

The categories of quality correspond to the logical forms of affirmation, negation and limitation. The latter are nothing but analytical relations of identity, exclusion and limitation (S is P; S excludes Q, S excludes an infinitesemal series of non S). In an inter-modal theoretical synthesis with the kinematical aspect of experience these logical forms can have no other function than that of an analytical-synthetical determination of

[pagina 511]
[p. 511]

the kinematical-mathematical meaning inherent in the aspect concerned. This is what Kant cannot accept because of his prejudice concerning the two exclusive sources of experience and his elimination of the cosmic order of time. So he ascribes a mathematical sense to the categories of quality themselves. The logical function of synthesis must fulfil the task of an inter-modal meaning-synthesis.

The same thing occurs in the case of Kant's categories of relation (inherence and subsistence, cause and effect, and interaction between the agens and that which undergoes the effect). But from the logical point of view the situation is more obscure here than in the case of the mathematical categories. The latter correspond indeed to different forms of analytical relations. As to the third class of Kant's categories this correspondence is doubtful. It is entirely lacking with regard to the first and the third categories. The category of inherence and subsistence is taken over from the traditional Aristotelian logic. It was closely bound to the metaphysical concept of substance and to the linguistic relation of subject and predicate. From the strictly logical viewpoint it must be seriously doubted whether it corresponds to a particular form of analytical relation. Apart from the metaphysical concept of substance it can hardly be different from the analytical relation of identity. Kant supposes that it is the logical form of the categorical judgment. But he fails to demonstrate this assertion.

The category of interaction between the agens and that which undergoes the effect (which is also taken over from Aristotle) lacks any correspondence to an analytical form of relation. It can never have an analytical meaning since it implies the reference to energy and its effects. Kant pretends that it corresponds to the logical form of a disjunctive judgment. The ground of this assertion remains quite obscureGa naar voetnoot1.

So it is only the second category of the third class, viz. that of causality, which has undoubted correspondence with a genuine form of analytical relation. Our provisional analysis of the modal

[pagina 512]
[p. 512]

structure of the logical aspect has shown that the analytical relation of causality has an analogical character: it is necessarily qualified by the analytical nucleus of the logical aspect. As an analytical law of every logical conclusion, it is nothing but the principium rationis sufficientis. Kant has rightly observed that it is the logical form of a hypothetical judgment. Even in an inter-modal synthesis with the energy-aspect of human experience the logical function of synthesis implied in the analytical relation of causality cannot give more than an analytical determination to the genuine causal relation of energy. Kant, however, ascribes the meaning of physical causality to the category of causality as a pure concept of the understanding. This appears from his statement that the concept of energy (Kraft) and that of action and undergoing an effect are to be derived from the category of causality and dependence, and that, as ‘Prädicabilien’ of this original notion, they have the same character of pure concepts of the understandingGa naar voetnoot1.

Thus Kant turns the (logical) principium rationis sufficientis into the ‘ground of possible experience’. The physical causal law is misinterpreted as the logical principle of the sufficient ground in its a priori relation to sensory phenomena in the succession of timeGa naar voetnoot2.

The complex inter-modal synthetical structure of the fundamental physical concept of causality is not for a moment discussed. On Kant's authority we must believe that it is nothing but a purely logical function of synthesizing a manifold given in the temporal form of sensory perception.

In the same way the three categories of modality are deduced (possibility-impossibility; actuality and non-actuality; necessity-chance). The conception of this class of categories is extremely typical of Kant's epistemological standpoint. It has an interesting history in immanence-philosophy which cannot be examined here in detail.

Aristotle's conception of the relations of possibility and actuality (δυνάμει ὄν and ἐνεϱγεία) had its foundation in the metaphysical form-matter schema. In Leibniz possibility was identified with the logically possible, the logically non-contradictory. The actual is taken to be identical with a selection from the logically possible realized by the deity, the ‘intellectus arche-

[pagina 513]
[p. 513]

typus’. This selection is the ‘compossible’, i.e. that which is compatible with all the rest and is the comparative best. In Kant, possibility, actuality and necessity become the logical categories of modality. As such they are alleged to be related a priori to sensory phenomenaGa naar voetnoot1. Within the cadre of human experience only the sensory is supposed to be actual, in its formal determination by the forms of intuition and thought; but actuality itself is a category of thought. The dogmatical character of this conception and its untenability can only appear from a structural analysis of the pre-theoretical experience of reality. But Kant's frame of mind causes him to ignore our pre-theoretical experience.

The problem of the inter-modal synthesis in Kant's doctrine of the ‘transcendental imagination’ (‘transszendentale Einbildungskraft’)Ga naar voetnoot2.

In his ‘transcendental logic’ Kant introduced the famous, but extremely obscure notion of the ‘transcendental imagination’. In the 24th section he discusses the application of the categories to ‘objects of sense in general’.

The ‘transcendental imagination’ also plays a central part in the chapter on the schematism. And it should consequently be supposed that we can understand the transcendental meaning of the category only from ‘the transcendental schema’, which has its origin in this ‘productive faculty of the imagination’. But it will appear that nothing is gained in this way.

In the opening passage of § 24 Kant has again explained the purely logical character of the synthesis in the categories with great emphasisGa naar voetnoot3.

He then continues as follows: ‘But as there is a certain form of a priori sensory intuition in the mind based on the recepti-

[pagina 514]
[p. 514]

vity of the representative faculty (sensibility), the understanding, as spontaneity, can determine inner sense by means of the manifold of given representations in accordance with the synthetic unity of apperception. In this way it can think synthetic unity of the apperception of the manifold of sensory intuition a priori - that being the pre-requisite to which all objects of our (human) intuition are necessarily subjected. In this way the categories, in themselves mere forms of thought, obtain objective reality, i.e. application to objects that can be given us in intuition. These objects, however, are only phenomena, for only of the latter can we have an intuition a priori’.

And now with great emphasis Kant distinguishes this a priori ‘synthesis of the manifold of sensory intuition’ as a ‘synthesis speciosa’ or ‘figurative synthesis’ from the merely logical synthesis (synthesis intellectualis). The latter is thought in the mere category in respect of the manifold of an intuition in general, and is called ‘Verstandesverbindung’ (combination through the understanding)Ga naar voetnoot2.

The above mentioned figurative synthesis in its relation to the transcendental unity of apperception is called ‘transcendental synthesis of the imagination’, in contradistinction to the merely logical synthesis.

What does Kant understand by ‘imagination’?Ga naar voetnoot3.

Ga naar voetnoot1
[pagina 515]
[p. 515]

In Hume's psychologistic critique of knowledge the imagination was considered to be the faculty that enables us to picture something not actually given in our sensory impressions. This imagination was conceived as subjected to the psychical laws of association only. Kant starts from this ‘empiricistic’ conception of the ‘imagination’ but only in order to show that the sensory phantasy itself is made possible only by the transcendental, figurative ‘synthesis of imagination’.

What place does Kant assign to the ‘imagination’ in his ‘transcendental logic’? Can this imagination perhaps elucidate the fundamental problem of epistemology, viz. the possibility of the inter-modal theoretical synthesis of meaning? Kant starts with defining the imagination as ‘the faculty of representing an object that is not present in our intuition.’ And then he says that on account of the subjective condition under which alone it can give a corresponding intuition to the concepts of the understanding, it belongs to receptive sensibility.

And, on the other hand, in so far as its synthesis is an act of spontaneity, Kant characterizes the imagination as an operation of the understanding on sensibility. As such it is the first application of the understanding to the objects of possible intuition and at the same time the basis of the exercise of all the other applications of that faculty. This shows clearly that it is precisely the synthetical activity of the productive phantasy which is ascribed to the logical function of thought. This fact is also acknowledged by Heidegger with regard to Kant's conception of the ‘imaginative faculty’ in the second edition of the ‘Critique of Pure Reason’Ga naar voetnoot1.

In the ‘transcendental operation of the imagination’ as a ‘figurative synthesis’ Kant sees a synthetical influence of the understanding on the ‘inner sense’ (Kr. d.r. V., p. 138) and the problem lies exactly in the possibility of this ‘influence’. The ‘inner sense’ is affected (affiziert) by the transcendental synthesis: ‘Now human understanding is not itself a faculty of intuitions, and cannot receive the latter, even if they are given in sensibility, into itself, in order to combine them as the manifold of its own intuition. Therefore its synthesis, considered in itself, is nothing but the unity of the act of which, as an act, it is aware even without the aid of sensibility. By means of the

[pagina 516]
[p. 516]

unity of this act, however, our understanding is capable of determining sensibility internally with regard to the manifold which may be given to it according to the form of sensory intuition. Thus, under the title of a transcendental synthesis of imagination, the understanding exercises this action on the passive subject, whose faculty it is; and we are therefore justified in saying that the inner sense is affected by this’Ga naar voetnoot1.

In contradistinction to psychological ‘empiricism’ Kant very carefully distinguishes the synthetical unity of ‘transcendental apperception’ from sensory intuition. The figurative synthesis, as a synthesis, takes its origin only in the understanding: ‘the understanding, therefore, does not find in this (i.e. the inner sense) such a conjunction of the manifold, but creates it by affecting this sense’Ga naar voetnoot2.

In his doctrine of the ‘synthesis speciosa’ Kant does not offer a solution of the basic problem of the inter-modal synthesis of meaning. He leaves it unsolved. Even if in his ‘transcendental imagination’ Kant had in mind an original systasis of logical and sensory functions - a possibility that we intend to discuss later on - the inter-functional synthesis would only have been ascribed to the isolated logical function of thought. Kant's conception of the synthesis, founded in the dogma concerning the formative autonomy of theoretical thought, left no room for any other solution.

So we may conclude that neither in his doctrine of the categories, nor in that of the ‘transcendental imagination’ did Kant consider the real problem of the intermodal meaning-synthesis.

[pagina 517]
[p. 517]

The doctrine of the categories does not belong to general epistemology but to the cosmological analysis of the modal meaning-structures.

To my criticism of Kant's doctrine of the categories I add a theoretical remark, the truth of which has already been established in the general theory of the modal spheres. That which the so-called critical epistemology treats in the chapter on the ‘categories of knowledge’ really belongs to the cosmological analysis of the modal structures of the law-spheres. It cannot be discussed in the dogmatical way of Kant's transcendental idealism. It is not possible to carry out a structural analysis of the modal aspects of experience, unless the universality of cosmic time, overarching all the modal functions, has been discovered.

The theory of the modal spheres, which proposes to give this structural analysis, must not be deterred by Kant's dogmatic restriction of scientific knowledge to the sensory aspect of experience. It should proceed with the execution of its imperative task of applying the analysis of the modal structures of meaning to all the law-spheres in their mutual coherence in time.

The epistemological problem proper in its restricted sense is concerned only with the question of the possibility of the inter-modal theoretical synthesis in which we grasp a modal aspect distinctly. And it is precisely this genuine epistemological problem which is constantly avoided by Kant.

§ 4 - How the problem of the inter-modal synthesis of meaning has been avoided in Kant's ‘Transcendental Doctrine of the Faculty of Judgment’.

Not before his ‘Transcendental Doctrine of the Faculty of Judgment’ does Kant seem to go into the problem of the inter-functional synthesis of meaning. The solution he offers is not really a critical solution, for he avoids the problem precisely at the crucial point. To demonstrate how ‘pure concepts of the understanding’ can be applied to phenomena at all, Kant formulates his well-known theory concerning the transcendental schematism of the ‘pure concepts of the understanding’: ‘It is now clear,’ he observes, ‘that there must be a third something of a similar nature to the category on the one hand, and to the phenomenon on the other, which makes it possible to apply the former to the latter. The mediating representation must be pure (i.e. void of anything empirical) and yet both intellectual and sensible. Such a representation is the transcendental schema.

[pagina 518]
[p. 518]

The concept of the understanding contains the pure synthetical unity of the manifold in general. Time, as the formal condition of the manifold content of the inner sense, and consequently of the combination of all representations, contains an a priori manifold in pure intuition. Now a transcendental determination of time is in so far of the same kind as a category (which constitutes its unity) as it is universal, and is based on a rule a priori. On the other hand it is in so far homogeneous with a phenomenon, as time is contained in every empirical representation of the manifold. This makes the application of the category to phenomena possible by means of the transcendental determination of time which, as the schema of the concepts of the understanding, mediates the subsumption of the phenomena under the category’Ga naar voetnoot1.

Kant's argument here simply contains a petitio principii. For the problem is: How is an inter-functional (inter-modal) synthesis between the logical categories and (psychical) sensory phenomena possible? The answer is: by means of the schema as the a priori (inter-functional) synthesis of a category and the psychical form of sensory intuition, time. But in this ‘schematizing of the categories of thought’, the inter-modal synthesis has apparently already been accomplished, just as it was pre-supposed in the transcendental imagination. We do not get any answer at all to the question: How is this inter-functional synthesis possible? In other words the possibility of the inter-functional synthesis between the logical category and the sensory phenomenon is explained by the inter-functional synthesis in the

[pagina 519]
[p. 519]

a priori schematized category. But this constitutes the petitio principii, since, on Kant's standpoint, the fundamental problem is exactly the ‘transcendental determination of time’.

The inter-functional synthesis pre-supposes a temporal coherence in the modal diversity of meaning, as well as a unity above the latter. Kant assumes an ultimate logical unity above a logical multiplicity in the ‘cogito’.

From the chapter on the schematism it appears that Kant must have seen the insufficiency of his conception of the unity of self-consciousness to explain the inter-functional relatedness of ‘the categories of thought’ to ‘sensory phenomena’.

In his Der Philosophische Kritizismus I, 478 (3rd ed.) Riehl observes: ‘The necessary combination of the pure concepts with the forms of intuition seems capable of demonstration without difficulty. Are not thought and intuition originally united in their common subject of consciousness?’Ga naar voetnoot1
Such an optimistic statement only proves that Riehl, who with regard to the conception of the cognitive synthesis perfectly agrees with Kant, has not realized the aporia (impasse) in which Kant's view of the transcendental unity of self-consciousness is involved. Without any really critical investigation of the possibility of an inter-functional meaning-synthesis he takes it for granted that as a matter of course the ‘cogito’ (in the Kantian sense of the transcendental logical subject) is the ground of the unity of thought and sensory intuitionGa naar voetnoot2. Yet Riehl admits: ‘Between the cognitive concepts and those of a purely logical combination there is not any essential difference, only one of application. Their use in purely logical propositions is analytical, that in judgments of experience is synthetical. In the former it is without any relation to the universal form of intuition (viz. time), in the latter it is in relation to this form’Ga naar voetnoot3.
Apparently Riehl did not see that in Kant's line of thought the same thing holds for the transcendental-logical unity of self-consciousness, and that it is precisely the relatedness of the latter to
[pagina 520]
[p. 520]
sensory intuition which has been only dogmatically posited by Kant. Riehl, too, fails to account for it in a truly critical consideration of the fundamental transcendental problem involved in the Kantian ‘cogito’. Therefore, I believe Riehl has not understood that in the chapter on the schematism Kant's critical conscience has been roused. This chapter must not be explained from the dependence of the great Königsberg thinker on the traditional view of the universality of the conceptsGa naar voetnoot1.

§ 5 - The problem of the inter-modal synthesis of meaning in the first edition of the ‘Kritik der reinen Vernunft’ according to Heidegger's interpretation.

Meanwhile Martin Heidegger in his important work Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik (1929) has made a remarkable attempt to show that in the first edition of the Kritik der reinen Vernunft Kant indeed assumed a common root of thought and sensory intuition, in the ‘transcendental faculty of the imagination’.

With this Heidegger again tackles a problem that has been of central importance in the whole of post-Kantian idealism. Heidegger calls this idealism rationalistic. To my mind, this is an error, and the reader may find the arguments for this opinion in the second part of Vol. I. Heidegger holds that the ‘productive imagination’ also functions as the root of practial reason in Kant's system. This view strongly reminds us of Fichte's interpretation of Kant. But Heidegger's interpretation did not take its origin in German idealism and has developed in a different direction, viz. in that of the modern ‘philosophy of existence’.

In the first edition of the Kr. d.r. V. Kant twice speaks of three subjective ‘sources’ as the activities of the soul's faculties.

From these the possibility of all experience is supposed to originate, viz. sense, imagination, and apperception (as ‘pure thought’)Ga naar voetnoot2.

[pagina 521]
[p. 521]

To each of these faculties he ascribes a special kind of synthesis: the ‘synthesis of apprehension in intuition’, the ‘synthesis of reproduction in imagination’, and the ‘synthesis of recognition in concepts’. This is seemingly a contradiction of the thesis already posited in the ‘Introduction’ (and repeated in the same context in which he distinguishes three faculties), according to which there are only two sources of knowledge. Here it is stated that we possess no others, although Kant mentions the possibility of a common root which is unknown to usGa naar voetnoot1.

In the second edition this seeming anomaly has already disappeared, and throughout we hear only of two cognitive functions whose common root is unknown to us.

And Heidegger admits that ‘Kant recoiled from this unknown root. In the second edition of the Kritik d.r. V. the transcendental faculty of the imagination, which appeared in the passionate impulse of the first plan of the book, was pushed back and re-interpreted - in favour of the understanding’Ga naar voetnoot2.

Heidegger is of the opinion that in the second edition the ‘transcendental faculty of the imagination’ has been maintained only nominally: ‘The synthesis is merely called “imagination” in so far as it is related to intuition, but at bottom it is the understanding’Ga naar voetnoot3.

This last assertion is indeed irrefutable. We have already

[pagina 522]
[p. 522]

shown this clearly. I would draw attention to Heidegger's admission: ‘If, as is done in the second edition, the transcendental imagination is cancelled as a special basic faculty; and if its function is transferred to the understanding as mere spontaneity, then there is no longer any possibility to understand pure sensibility and pure thought with regard to their unity in one finite human reason, or even to make this unity a problem’Ga naar voetnoot1.

This last remark perfectly agrees with the whole of my previous argument. In advance, however, I must warn against Heidegger's sharp (though unwarranted) distinction between the epistemological problem and that of the ‘Sein des Seienden’. I must do so on the grounds given in the third part of the first Volume of this work. If Heidegger only meant to oppose the positivistic neo-Kantian tendency to deprive the transcendental motive in Kant's Kritik der reinen Vernunft of its depth, I might agree with Heidegger to a certain extent. At least, if he meant to emphasize the fact that the Kritik der reinen Vernunft was really written for the sake of the metaphysics of practical reason. Any attempt, therefore, to lay the point of gravitation of Kant's critical philosophy in ‘theoretical reason’ would be an intrinsical falsification of Kant's problems. Against such a background I am willing to agree that there is a kernel of truth in Heidegger's thesis that the Kritik has nothing to do with a ‘theory of knowledge’, in the sense of a pure theory concerning the possibility of mathematical natural science. That is to say, I could agree with its basic intention, and that in spite of its exaggeration. The Critique of Pure Reason has doubtless an epistemological character. But its ultimate aim is not a mere epistemological foundation of mathematics and natural science.

Ultimately Kant's critique of the theoretical cognitive faculty is orientated to his idealistic conception of the super-temporal noumenon.

This is a fundamental theme of the traditional metaphysica generalis, which found the ὄν ἧ ὄν, as the transcendent, immanent in the theoretical νοῦς.. Kant was the first to orientate this theme to the religious root of the Humanistic ideal of personal-

[pagina 523]
[p. 523]

ity. In his critical philosophy it can only be interpreted according to the dualistic cosmonomic Idea in which it is founded. The sharp contrast between phenomena and noumena, which he scrupulously maintains in his Kritik der reinen Vernunft, is a proof that the great Königsberg thinker does not for a moment doubt the absolute transcendence of the practical Ideas above the temporal world. Accordingly as he rejects the claims of the speculative science-ideal to the province of metaphysics, he all the more clings to his unshakable rational faith in the homo noumenon elevated above all time. The decline of the Humanistic self-consciousness, manifest in the philosophy of existence, which originated from the problems of irrationalistic historism, is nowhere to be seen in Kant's philosophy.

How Heidegger approaches Kant's critical transcendental philosophy.

Heidegger wants to understand Kant from the very point of view of this modern state of decline. In this view the selfhood in our self-consciousness is interpreted with reference to its ‘innermost original essence’ as ‘time itself’. It is, however, hardly right to efface the whole (metaphysical) contrast between phenomena and noumena which is so fundamental in Kant's line of thought. Heidegger's maxim for the interpretation of a philosophical system cannot make this eradication acceptable. He lays down as a rule that a correct interpretation should not merely stick to what a thinker has really expressed in words, but should penetrate to ‘that which is implied in the words’Ga naar voetnoot1.

For although what Heidegger remarks is true, namely, that ‘the power and light of a guiding Idea should impel and lead the interpretation’Ga naar voetnoot2, this Idea should not be imposed on the system that is being investigated. It may only be the cosmonomic Idea which Kant himself has laid at the foundation of his Critiques, although he should not be aware of it. Heidegger, however, bases Kant's philosophic thought in an entirely different cosmonomic Idea, viz. the irrationalistic and historicistic basic Idea of his own existentialism. Thus he falls into an arbitrary hermeneutic method that he himself has erroneously elevated to a maxim of correct interpretation, when he remarks: ‘However, in order to extort from what the words say that which they

[pagina 524]
[p. 524]

are intended to sayGa naar voetnoot1, every interpretation must necessarily have recourse to violence’Ga naar voetnoot2.

The result is then that the interpretation of Kant's Kritik der reinen Vernunft becomes an introduction to Heidegger's own philosophy of ‘Sein und Zeit’, which no doubt is itself highly interesting.

According to Heidegger's interpretation the ‘transcendental imagination’, as the supposed root of the two Kantian ‘stems’ of knowledge, must be identical with ‘pure reason’, both in its ‘theoretical’ and in its ‘practical operation’. It is identical also with the ‘pure finite selfhood’ whose ‘Dasein’ (i.e. existence) is rooted in time itself. Pure reason must then be conceived as ‘pure receptive spontaneity’, as ‘pure sensory reason’. The synthesis considered by Kant as the central theme of the entire Kritik der reinen Vernunft, is reinterpreted by Heidegger as an ontological synthesis. According to him it must not be conceived as the mere conjunction into a unity of an isolated sensory intuition and isolated ‘pure concepts of thought’, but should be understood as an a priori, non-empirical disclosure of the ontological structure of what isGa naar voetnoot3.

The essential character of the finiteness of human knowledge, according to Heidegger, is that human understanding does not create its ‘objects’ but receives them. For human life (das Dasein) is at the mercy of ‘das Vorhandene’ i.e. given nature; human life is dependent on it and only rises superior to the ‘Vorhandene’ because of its capability to understand that which is. For this purpose human ‘Dasein’ a priori, and previous to all experience, designs an image of the being of what is. ‘Thus the question about the possibility of an a priori synthesis more and more concentrates on the problem: how can a finite being, which, as such, is delivered to what is (at hand) and is dependent on the reception of what is given, know the latter before any reception of what is, i.e. intuit it without, however, being its ‘creator’?Ga naar voetnoot4.

[pagina 525]
[p. 525]

Heidegger's conception of transcendence.

Heidegger wants to read these problems also in Kant's Kritik der reinen Vernunft. The transcendence of the selfhood then remains of a temporal character. It is only the transcendence of the temporal finite human ‘Dasein’ above the ‘Vorhandene’ (the sensible things that are given), but it is not an ideal transcendence above time itself. Time as ‘pure intuition’, as ‘pure self-affection’ is the essence of the finite human selfhood. If the selfhood, the I-ness is found in the ‘transcendental imagination’, it is identical with ‘time’ as ‘pure intuition’. In the ‘transcendental imagination’ must be sought the original essential unity of the ‘stems’ of knowledge that Kant isolated at first, but which, as such, could not be fully grasped. These ‘stems’ of knowledge are sensory intuition and logical thought. The ‘transcendental imagination’ must be understood as the ‘formative medium’ (bildende Mitte) of the two ‘stems of knowledge from which they originate as from the primitive original synthesis’. Heidegger here shows a much deeper insight into the real problems of the cognitive synthesis than Kant's most articulate modern followers. The latter simply eulogize Kant's discovery of ‘the synthetical character of all objective knowledge’ and his ‘Copernican deed’, without penetrating to the crucial questions implied in his transcendental idealism. Perhaps Heidegger's superiority in this respect is due to the fact that, however much he may start from the philosophical immanence-standpoint, he approaches Kant from the modern state of decline of the Humanistic ideals of personality and science. In Kant these two still function as the unshakable pillars of his cosmonomic Idea. His faith in the autonomy of theoretical reason caused him to overlook the most fundamental problems of a transcendental critique of human knowledge. Heidegger, who is no longer biased by this dogmatic prejudice, was confronted with the real problem of the inter-functional synthesis and tries to solve it in his own way, though he ascribes this solution to Kant himself.

Heidegger's interpretation of Kant changes that philosopher's thought considerably both as to its foundation and its essence. And yet Heidegger's book is extremely valuable as an attempt to think out the problems of Kant's Kritik der reinen Vernunft with regard to the fundamental chapter on the ‘synthesis’.

[pagina 526]
[p. 526]

The problem of the primary (ontological) synthesis in Heidegger.

The question is: to what extent does Heidegger's interpretation approach the fundamental problem regarding the possibility of the inter-modal synthesis of meaning?

For the answer we must first recall what Heidegger means by the fundamental synthesis. He seeks the primitive original synthesis in the transcendental imagination, i.e. in the formative medium between ‘pure thought’ and ‘pure intuition’.

This shows that Heidegger is aware of the fact that every theoretical isolation of the ‘understanding’ and ‘sensitivity’ presupposes a primary inter-modal synthesis. We acknowledge this without implying that Heidegger has really understood Kant's view. But has Heidegger also seen that we can only isolate a modal function theoretically within the fulness of the temporal meaning-systasis and by starting from it?

Only against the background of the primary cosmic temporal coherence of meaning can the fundamental problem concerning the possibility of theoretical synthesis be conceived in its true sense. If this primary temporal coherence of the modal aspects of experience is to be acknowledged as a basic fact, a philosopher must break with the immanence-standpoint.

For this standpoint is based upon an overt or hidden hypostasis of theoretical thought. Such a break is not to be expected from Heidegger who seeks the selfhood in the temporal (historically conceived) ‘Dasein’. He writes:

‘The ontical only becomes accessible to a finite being on the basis of a preliminary willingness to let something take up a position as an entity opposite to us. Thus the ontical possibly presenting itself to us is beforehand drawn within the unifying horizon of a possible belonging together. This a priori unifying unity must anticipate that which presents itself to us, at the same time opposing itself to the latter. That which presents itself, however, has already beforehand been encompassed by the temporal horizon held up to it in pure intuition. The anticipating unifying unity of the pure understanding must therefore also beforehand have united itself with pure intuition. This a priori united whole of pure intuition and pure understanding “constitutes” the scope of our willingness to let an entity take up a position opposite to us. In this scope all the ontical will be able to present itself to us. In view of this totality of transcendence the point is to show how - and this means at the same time

[pagina 527]
[p. 527]

“that” - pure understanding and pure intuition are a priori interdependent’Ga naar voetnoot1.

What appears clearly from this quotation is that Heidegger also thinks reality is only accessible to the selfhood in the theoretical abstraction of that which is opposed to the logical function as a phenomenon (the ‘gegenständliche’). The fact that being only manifests itself to us as a phenomenon - which is identical with the ‘object’ (‘Gegenstand’) to Heidegger - reveals the finiteness, the temporal character of human knowledge which has been delivered to what is given (das Vorhandene) in nature. The ‘phenomenon’ (the empirical ‘Vorhandene’) he considers as the Platonic μὴ ὄν, the relative nothing, which only receives its ontological (not ontic) being through the ‘pure synthesis’ of the transcendental imagination.

With reference to the first edition of Kant's Kritik d.r. V. Heidegger has raised the question: How is the primary ontological synthesis possible in which the image of the ‘Sein des Seienden’ is planned? In his system of thought this question is as unanswerable as the fundamental problem regarding the epistemological synthesis was to Kant

For Heidegger also eliminates the cosmic order of time and even merges the selfhood into time, to which, however, he does not ascribe its cosmic all-sided meaning. This distinguishes his view from Kant's practical (ethical) metaphysics which maintained the selfhood as the super-temporal, super-sensory noumenon.

Nevertheless, Heidegger makes a serious attempt to explain the possibility of the primary (really theoretical) meaning-synthesis between ‘pure thought’ and ‘pure sensibility’. He does

[pagina 528]
[p. 528]

so by ‘interpreting’ Kant's line of argument in the style of his own existentialistic philosophy. ‘Pure thought’ and ‘pure sensibility’ must be conceived as modi of the ‘transcendental imagination’, which in essence is time and selfhood. The three modi that Kant distinguishes in the cognitive synthesis, in the first edition of his Kritik der reinen VernunftGa naar voetnoot1, are essentially no more than the threefold unity of time as the present, the past and the future. Thus the problem regarding the primary meaning-synthesis seems to have been solved at one masterly stroke.

Time and the ‘cogito’ (as the transcendental unity of self-consciousness) are no longer opposed to one another as irreconcilable contrasts: they are identical:

‘In laying the foundations of his metaphysics, Kant was the first to explain both time as such and the “I think” as such transcendentally. He did this in such a radical way that he brought them together in their original identity, however, without explicitly considering this identity as such’Ga naar voetnoot2.

For sensibility means finite intuition with Kant. Its transcendental form (‘time’) is ‘pure receptivity’. The ‘inner sense’ receives nothing ‘from without’, but everything from its own self. As time it is ‘pure self-affection’Ga naar voetnoot3, as Kant qualifies it. But, according to Heidegger, this ‘pure self-affection’ is the transcendental basic structure of the finite ego itself, and the finite ego is nothing but the ‘pure understanding’, the ‘transcendental unity of self-consciousness’ which as such must be understood as ‘pure sensuous understanding’, as ‘purely receptive spontaneity’.

Is this explanation a true solution of the central problem of the intermodal synthesis of meaning? Certainly not. Neither in Heidegger's reasoning nor in Kant's has the genuine kernel of the problem been conceived.

In Kant the real problem of the inter-functional meaning-synthesis only arises as an after-thought, after he had begun to

[pagina 529]
[p. 529]

absolutize the primary meaning-synthesis which had been the pre-supposition of his analysis of the sources of knowledge. Heidegger, whose penetration is deeper, acknowledges that in the isolation of the ‘sources’ of knowledge, ‘pure synthesis’ is already operative. But as soon as he is himself confronted with the problem, and has to account for the original meaning-synthesis, he makes both cognitive functions flow together into a supposed identity in time as ‘pure intuition’.

If the two cognitive functions in time are one and the same, the possibility of a real synthesis has not been explained. It has even been cancelled. In the cognitive theoretical concept the inter-modal synthesis of meaning pre-supposes the analytical ἔποχή, the abstraction of the continuity of cosmic time. Even cosmic time guarantees only the temporal coherence, but never the deeper identity of the functions. How then can time as a ‘pure form of sensibility’ perform this task? Designating Kant's ‘pure understanding’ as ‘pure sensory understanding’ will result in a kind of dialectic that Kant would certainly have rejected as emphatically as he could. The real issue is the possibility of a synthesis between logical and sensory modalities and Kant did not for a moment contemplate letting sensibility and understanding flow together dialectically. It is true, he did not pay due regard to the modal aspects as such, and in the first edition Kant still works with the ‘genus proximum’ of thought and sensory intuition, viz. ‘representation in general’Ga naar voetnoot1. But when Heidegger looks upon this fact as an indication of the internal affinity of the two ‘cognitive stems’Ga naar voetnoot2, he forgets that the genus-concept applied to the modal aspects is of a logical origin.

Heidegger's conception of the ‘transcendental imagination’ as the root of the two abstracted ‘stems of knowledge’ obtained in a theoretical analysis and synthesis of meaning, results in an undeniable dialectic. The cause is that it seeks this common root in time, apparently conceived here in the Kantian sense. It tries to solve the problem of the primary synthesis between ‘pure thought’ and ‘pure sensibility’ (= time) by proclaiming ‘pure sensibility’ to be the origin of ‘pure thought’Ga naar voetnoot3.

[pagina 530]
[p. 530]

I pass by the internal contradiction into which Heidegger gets

[pagina 531]
[p. 531]

involved by first calling the selfhood the origin of time and then identifying it with timeGa naar voetnoot1.

I want only to lay strong emphasis on the fact that Heidegger after all makes one of the ‘stems of knowledge’ in its supposed ‘purity’ into the origin of the other. He does so notwithstanding his search after a deeper root of ‘pure sensibility’ and ‘pure thought’ which was to make the inter-modal meaning-synthesis possible. He overlooked the fact that ‘pure sensibility’ is at best a theoretical abstraction originating solely from the analysis and inter-modal synthesis of meaning, and unable to account for this synthesis. Even Heidegger's ‘existential time’ is not cosmic time guaranteeing the continuous coherence between the modal aspects of experience. If he had had real insight into cosmic time, he would never have sought the transcendence of the selfhood in the inner experience of the ‘ex-sistere’, in the historical time-aspect with its anticipatory future. In time our selfhood only expresses itself in the refraction of meaning and the coherence

[pagina 532]
[p. 532]

of its modal functions. Time cannot be the deeper identity of the modal functions, not even in its cosmic continuity. It cannot contain the totality of meaning but refracts it in the modal and typical meaning-diversity.

Is there really a point of contact in the first edition of the Kritik der reinen Vernunft for Heidegger's interpretation?

Is there really a basis to be found in the first edition of Kant's Kr. d.r. V. for Heidegger's interpretation? I think we should view the facts like this: Kant actually started from a primary formal unity of logical thought and sensibility, not only in the first edition but also in the second. The transcendental imagination can indeed have no other function in Kant's argument than that of a connecting link between the two ‘stems of knowledge’. The assertion that Kant considered the imagination as the ‘hidden root’ of both ‘stems’ is already refuted by Kant's critical starting-point. If it is a question of a hidden root, we can only formulate speculative hypotheses about it. And in the Preface to the first edition Kant rejects such hypotheses with great sharpness. I refer to the following utterance:

‘And then certitude and clearness are the two indispensable requirements which the form of such an enquiry must answer, and which the author who risks such a ticklish job should try to fulfil. As regards certitude I have come to the conclusion that in this kind of studies it is in no way permissible to express a mere opinion, and that anything resembling an hypothesis is inadmissable... and should be removed as soon as it is discovered’Ga naar voetnoot1.

In the same Preface Kant writes about the second chapter of the ‘Transcendental Analytics’. This chapter contains the passage quoted above concerning ‘sense’, ‘imagination’ and ‘apperception’ as the three original faculties of the soul. In the Preface Kant observes:
‘The view taken here, which goes somewhat deeply into the sub-
[pagina 533]
[p. 533]
ject, has two aspects. The one is related to the objects of the pure understanding. It is intended to establish the objective validity of its a priori concepts and to render these intelligible, and for this reason it is an essential part of my work. The other aims at considering the pure understanding itself as regards its possibility and the cognitive faculties on which it rests, consequently from the subjective viewpoint.
And although this latter orientation is very important with regard to my principal aim, it does not form an essential element in it (Italics are mine). For the principal question remains: what and how much can the understanding and reason know apart from any experience? and not: how is the faculty of thought itself possible? The latter question is as it were an inquiry into the cause of a given effect, and in so far resembles in some degree a hypothesis (although, as I shall show later on, it is not really so).
Yet here I seem to permit myself the liberty to pronounce a mere opinion, and therefore the reader ought also to be free to hold a different opinion. In this connection I would remind the reader that in case my subjective deduction, contrary to my expectation, should not have fully convinced him, the objective deduction at which I chiefly aim in this work retains its full force’Ga naar voetnoot1.
Consequently it is not in accordance with Kant's intention if the subjective way of deduction is played off against the objective method and is even made the centre of Kant's problem.

The thesis of the twofold origin of all cognition (viz. sensibility and understanding) was considered by Kant to be so little contradictory to the other thesis about the three original sources

[pagina 534]
[p. 534]

(functions of the soul) containing the pre-requisites of the possibility of all experience, that he immediately coordinates the second thesis with the first in the section entitled: Transition to the Transcendental Deduction of the Categories. It is contrary to the fundamental principles of a correct interpretation if a fundamental contradiction is supposed to exist here. The ‘transcendental power of the imagination’ is not a third ‘stem of knowledge’ in the first edition. Kant much rather ascribes it to the ‘pure sensibility’, which relates to the ‘transcendental unity of the apperception’ (the logical form of self-consciousness), which only renders it intellectual. This is clearly seen in the ‘third section of the deduction of the pure concepts of the understanding’ in which Kant tries to show the internal foundation of the unity of knowledge.

He had already discussed the three kinds of synthesis, and now he follows a line of reasoning that descends from the ‘transcendental unity of the apperception’. Next he follows a course of argument in the opposite direction by starting from the empirical phenomenon in observation and perception. Heidegger has investigated these two methods very minutely. Arriving at the end of the second method, Kant writes:

‘For the constant and permanent “I” (of pure apperception) forms the correlatum of all our representations in so far as it is at all possible to become conscious of them. The whole of consciousness belongs to an all-comprehensive pure apperception, just as all sensory intuition belongs to a pure inner intuition, viz. time. It is this apperception which must be added to pure imagination in order to render its function intellectual. For in itself the synthesis of imagination is at all times sensible though it is exercised a priori, because it connects the manifold only in the way it appears in intuition, e.g., the shape of a triangle’Ga naar voetnoot1.

So, also in the first edition the ‘transcendental unity of self-

[pagina 535]
[p. 535]

consciousness’ has decidedly not been conceived to be sensible.

And then follows Kant's definition of the ‘pure imagination’ which is fundamentally identical with that of the second edition:

‘So we have a faculty of pure imagination as the fundamental faculty of the human soul on which all knowledge is based. By its means we combine the manifold of intuition with the condition of the necessary unity of pure apperception. These two extremes, viz. sensibility and understanding, must necessarily hang together by means of this transcendental function of the imagination;...’Ga naar voetnoot1.

The question how the ‘transcendental imagination’ was enabled to perform this mediating function was never answered by Kant, neither in the first edition, nor in the second. This leaves only one possible explanation of Kant's argument: Kant started from a necessary systasis viz. that of ‘pure sensibility’ and ‘pure thought’ (but not from the real meaning-systasis in cosmic time), and misinterpreted the primary meaning-synthesis from which he started as a systatic datumGa naar voetnoot2,Ga naar voetnoot3

This is the dogmatic standpoint which from the start I have tried to point out in Kant's epistemology.

So long as the prejudice of the self-sufficiency of theoretical thought is adhered to, the transcendental and the transcendent conditions of all theoretical knowledge must necessarily be eliminated the cosmic temporal order, as well as the insight into this order and the transcendence of the religious selfhood above cosmic time. The primary synthesis between the understanding and sensibility was not recognized by Kant as a real problem in the chapter on the schematism. He only thought problematic the possibility of subsuming the so-called ‘empirical’ phenomena under the pure concepts of the understanding. But he was unable to raise the deeper problem behind

[pagina 536]
[p. 536]

it, viz. about the conditions under which ‘pure thought’ and ‘pure sensibility’ can be synthetized. He could not ask this, because the mere raising of such a problem would have meant relinquishing the immanence-standpoint based on the faith in the self-sufficiency of ‘reason’ in all theoretical epistemological questions.

In the supposedly ‘given’ unity of pure thought and pure intuition the logical function remained the true law-giver and determining factor in Kant's view.

Heidegger, approaching Kant from the modern state of decline of the Humanistic self-consciousness, saw the problem as an abyss. But he, too, was unable to pose it in a truly critical way. For he clung to the immanence-standpoint even more tightly than Kant had done. In proclaiming time to be ‘pure sensibility’ and the very essence of the selfhood and hence the root of the Kantian ‘stems of knowledge’, he is blind to the truth that this ‘pure time’ is itself a theoretical abstraction. It pre-supposes the inter-modal meaning-synthesis of which it is intended to render an account. In the supposed unity of pure thought and pure intuition he ascribed only a subservient position to the former. But he did not realize that in the last instance he, too, sought his Archimedean point in a theoretical synthesis.

A modal function can never be the root of all the functions. And it is never possible to demonstrate the possibility of the primary synthesis by means of an original ‘pure synthesis’.

§ 6 - The functionalistic ‘Thesis of Consciousness’ (‘Satz des Bewusztseins’) and the view of the limits of experience in the light of the cosmonomic idea.

In the relentless struggle against speculative metaphysics the Kantian conception of experience has become the shibboleth between the supposedly ‘critical’ and the ‘dogmatical’ trends of thought. This conception was precipitated in the so-called ‘Satz des Bewusztseins’ (the thesis of consciousness) or the ‘Satz der Immanenz’ (the thesis of immanence).

According to the transcendental-idealistic view of this ‘Satz’ there is no possibility of any experience outside the limits of the transcendental consciousness. All that we have knowledge of is necessarily immanent in the transcendental consciousness.

Is not this thesis really a truism whose validity is so universal and elevated above any prejudice that every intelligent mind

[pagina 537]
[p. 537]

has to admit it, no matter on what cosmonomic Idea his philosophy is founded?

It would be so, if it were not necessary for us to give an account of the meaning of our words. For, if anywhere, the bitter wisdom of Mephisto holds good here: ‘Mit Worten lässt sich trefflich streiten.’ [Words are admirably suited to carry on a debate.]

The meaning of the ‘Satz des Bewusztseins’ depends on the meaning which phenomenalistic and transcendental-idealistic immanence-philosophy ascribe to the words ‘consciousness’ and ‘experience’. The philosophic sense of these words is determined by the starting-point of philosophical thought.

The influence of the Kantian conception of ‘empirical reality’ in the normative special sciences.

The Kantian conception of consciousness has resulted in misinterpreting ‘empirical reality’ in a functionalistic manner and in narrowing the limits of the possibility of experience in an unjustified (because sense-less) way. That is why Mephisto's scepsis is necessary with regard to the ‘Satz des Bewusztseins’ just as much as with regard to every other ‘axiom’ of immanence-philosophy.

Especially in the normative special sciences the functionalistic view of ‘empirical reality’ as the synthetically arranged sensorily perceptible has become a deep-rooted pernicious prejudice. It is almost impossible to convey one's thoughts to one's colleagues in an intelligible way, if one has broken with this prejudice. Whatever does not belong to ‘empirical’ reality in the sense mentioned is considered as a construction of thought. In such an ‘empirical’ reality the ‘juridical person’ has no place: it is therefore a construction of thought, a ‘form of thought’. Only in this empirical ‘reality’ does the law of causality hold. Causality is per se a ‘category of the experience of nature’. In ‘empirical reality’ the will is only a psychical a-normative factum. When jurisprudence can do nothing with the psychological concept of will, the juridical concept of volition is considered to be a technical construction of thought, or a ‘form of thought’. The territory of the state is nothing but the sensorily perceptible land and water within its geographical boundaries. Anything that is not sensorily perceptible in it, does not belong to ‘empirical reality’, but is a normative construction of thought, etc.

[pagina 538]
[p. 538]

All the modal aspects of reality contained in the normative law-spheres are transformed into psycho-psychical phenomena in behalf of this functionalistic conception of experience. The normative principles of these law-spheres are hypostatized into super-temporal ideas according to their super-subjective meaning, insofar as under the tyranny of naturalism they do not share in the fate of the subject-side of the aspects concerned. Or they are deprived of their true meaning and proclaimed normative ‘forms of thought’.

For the benefit of the ‘Satz des Bewusztseins’ naïve experience is fundamentally and essentially misinterpreted. In truth the Humanistic conception of experiential reality tyrannizes science by means of the prejudice of the Humanistic immanence-stand-point.

The ‘Satz des Bewusztseins’, of course, also allows of other interpretations than the critical-Kantian one. In a coarser, psychologized sense it is found in the so-called ‘empiricistic-positivistic’ schools of thought. In Husserl's phenomenology, as we know it from his posthumous writings, the thesis assumes a new transcendental-idealistic meaning freed from the Kantian exclusively natural-scientific conception of experience.

But in whatever shade of meaning this thesis may be propounded from the immanence-standpoint, it is always oriented to a definite type of the cosmonomic Idea of immanence-philosophy. Kant's conception of empirical reality is entirely dominated by his dualistic Humanistic cosmonomic Idea. The normative aspects of reality fall outside of ‘experience’, because the realm of experience is allotted to the mechanistic science-ideal, to which the autonomy of the free personality must not be sacrificed. For this reason it must be called a superficial procedure for Christian thought to assume that it can accept the ‘critical’ conception of experience of Kant's Kritik der reinen Vernunft and at the same time reject his Kritik der praktischen Vernunft. For Kant's ethics and his theory of experience form an indissoluble whole so that the one stands or falls with the other. The functionalistic restriction of experience to the horizon of Kant's transcendental consciousness does not simply mean its restriction to the ‘phenomena’, but the complete theoretical destruction of all possibility of experience.

This thesis may seem to be strange at first sight. But it will no longer be so to anyone who has assimilated our previous expositions of the meaning-character of created reality.

[pagina 539]
[p. 539]

Why is it meaning-less to restrict the datum of experience to the sensory matter of sensory impressions? Because this thesis is self-destructive, insofar as Kant's conception of matter is the product of theoretical abstraction. What has been abstracted can never be the datum. The sensory function of intuition has a modal meaning by which it is integrated into the full temporal reality and which offers an insurmountable resistance to any attempt to make the sensory aspect of experience theoretically independant. Such an attempt cannot be supposed to leave at least the sensory aspect of experience intact, but it cancels this aspect and lands us in ‘pure nothingness’ (das reine Nichts). If the human selfhood is capable of consciously experiencing the sensory aspect of reality in its subject-object relations, it necessarily experiences this sensory aspect in the cosmic temporal meaning-coherence.

This conscious experience is a quite different thing from the subjective undergoing of sense-impressions found in animals. And if the human selfhood transcends cosmic time, not a single aspect of temporal reality can transcend the self-consciousness operative in all human experience.

Speculative metaphysics has invented the splitting up of temporal reality into a noumenon and a phenomenon. The phenomenalistic conception of human experience remains tainted with the (fundamentally religious) prejudice of this metaphysics which is recognisable even in the disguise of a positivism claiming to be free of all manner of preoccupation.

There is nothing in experience that has been given us without the psychical function of consciousness. But if nothing outside of this function had been given us, we should not have been given anything at all, not even the sensible itself.

This thesis is merely the counterpart of the thesis we have formulated in the Prolegomena: We cannot know anything without logical thought, but if we were not were able to know anything outside of logical thought, we could not know anything at all. For not a single aspect of experience can exist outside of the cosmic coherence of meaning, and where meaning ceases, there is an end of created reality and of all human experience.

Let the attempt be made to take the phenomenalistic conception of experience seriously and then to abstract everything that is of a non-sensory and a non-logical character in our naïve experience of reality. The experiment will appear to be impossible without a complexity of shiftings of meaning. By means of these

[pagina 540]
[p. 540]

all kinds of things are supposed to be implied in the sensible and the logical that were not to be found in them originally.

But anyone who in the future wants to defend the phenomenolist conception of experience in all seriousness will at least have to give an account of the meaning of the sensory and the logical aspect.

This is certainly not done by means of the neo-Kantian argument that it is transcendental logical thought which determines all sensory matter of experience and in this way creates the meaning of the latter.

The ‘critical method’ will have to become more critical, if it wants to maintain its claim to the self-assumed honour of being ‘critical’.

Conclusions

Our expositions justify the conclusion that the ‘conception of experience’ adhered to on the standpoint of the functionalistic ‘Satz cles Bewusztseins’ (the thesis of consciousness) must be rejected if the insight into the possibility of cognizing the modal functions is not to be precluded a priori. The conception of experience mentioned above is based on a fundamental misinterpretation both of the cosmic and the cosmological self-consciousness, of which the latter is founded in the former. Besides, the data of experience are also misconstrued. They have been given to our self-consciousness to which all modal aspects of temporal reality are related. They have not been given to the sensory function of this self-consciousness, and they are never of a functional but of a cosmic-systatic character.

The cosmic and cosmological intuition of time can never be identified with a supposed ‘pure sensibility’, or with ‘a form of sensory intuition’.

Human experience of temporal reality in principle has no specific functional boundaries, because in the root of self-consciousness it transcends time itself. All the modal aspects of temporal reality are at least in principle immanent in possible experience, immanent in the cosmological self-consciousness. In the last instance it is not some abstract functions of consciousness but the fulness of self-consciousness which experiences the modal meaning-functions in cosmic time as its own. This insight means the final liberation of epistemology from the prejudices of immanence-philosophy.

The assertion that our experience is restricted to the sensory

[pagina 541]
[p. 541]

and logical aspects of reality, in other words, that we can have no experience of the other meaning-functions in their original character, is absolutely contrary to the datum of our cosmic self-consciousness.

It would be a matter for surprise that epistemology could so long accept this thesis as an axiom, if behind this prejudice we had not discovered the dualistic-Humanistic cosmonomic Idea with its polar tension between the science-ideal and that of personality.

voetnoot1
We should bear in mind that the attitude of thought, necessarily determined by the religious attitude of the self-hood, transcends theoretical thought, whose direction it controls. The identification of the supra-theoretical with the theoretical attitude of thought should be scrupulously avoided.
voetnoot1
By ‘lack of logical integrety’ is of course not meant an ethical, but only a theoretic-logical qualification.

voetnoot1
Cf. especially the ‘Vorrede’ of the 1st edition of the Kr. d.r. V. Here, entirely in the spirit of the time of the Enlightenment, Kant says: ‘Unser Zeitalter ist das eigentliche Zeitalter der Kritik, der sich alles unterwerfen musz. Religion durch ihre Heiligkeit und Gesetzgebung durch ihre Majestät wollen sich gemeinlich derselben entziehen. Aber alsdann erregen sie gerechten Verdacht wider sich und können auf unverstellte Achtung nicht Anspruch machen, die die Vernunft nur demjenigen bewilligt, was ihre freie und öffentliche Prüfung hat aushalten können.’ [Our age is the age of criticism, to which everything must be subjected. The sanctity of religion, and the majesty of legislation, may seek to exempt themselves from the examination of this tribunal.
But, if they are exempted, they awaken just suspicion, and cannot lay claim to the sincere respect which reason accords only to that which has stood the test of a free and open examination.]

voetnoot1
impressions.
voetnoot2
Kr. d.r. V. 2nd Edit. (Grosz. Wilh. Ernst Ausg.) p. 59, ‘In der transszendentalen Aesthetik also werden wir zuerst die Sinnlichkeit isolieren, dadurch dass wir alles absondern was der Verstand durch seine Begriffe dabei denkt, damit nichts als empirische Anschauung übrig bleibe.’

voetnoot1
op. cit., p. 123: ‘Daher zeigt sich hier eine Schwierigkeit, die wir im Felde der Sinnlichkeit nicht antrafen, wie nämlich subjektive Bedingungen des Denkens sollten objektive Gültigkeit haben, d.i. Bedingungen der Möglichkeit aller Erkenntnis der Gegenstände abgeben: denn ohne Funktionen des Verstandes können allerdings Erscheinungen in der Anschauung gegeben werden.’

voetnoot1
op. cit., p. 122.
voetnoot1
Kr. d.r. V., Transsz. Logik, ch. II § 15: ‘Man wird hier leicht gewahr, dasz diese Handlung’ (viz. the synthesis) ‘ursprünglich einig und für alle Verbindung gleichgeltend sein müsse, und dass die Auflösung, Analysis, die ihr Gegenteil zu sein scheint, sie doch jederseit voraussetze; denn wo der Verstand vorher nichts verbunden hat, da kann er auch nichts auflösen, weil es nur durch ihn als verbunden der Vorstellungskraft hat gegeben werden können.’
voetnoot2
ibid.: ‘alle Verbindung, wir mögen uns ihrer bewuszt werden oder nicht, es mag eine Verbindung des Mannigfaltigen der Anschauung oder mancherlei Begriffe, und an der ersteren der sinnlichen oder nichtsinnlichen Anschauung sein, [ist] eine Verstandeshandlung.’
voetnoot3
i.e. higher than in the quantitative category of unity.
voetnoot4
op. cit., p. 123: ‘Also müssen wir diese Einheit noch höher suchen, nämlich in demjenigen was selbst den Grund der Einheit verschiedener Begriffe in Urteilen, mithin der Möglichkeit des Verstandes sogar in seinem logischen Gebrauche enthält.’ (Italics are mine).
voetnoot1
Read: generated (with Vaihinger).
voetnoot2
Op. cit., p. 125: ‘nur dadurch, dass ich das Mannigfaltige’ (i.e. der Vorstellungen) ‘in einem Bewusstsein begreifen kann, nenne ich dieselbe insgesamt meine Vorstellungen; denn sonst würde ich ein so vielfärbiges verschiedenes Selbst haben als ich Vorstellungen habe, deren ich mir bewusst bin. Synthetische Einheit des Mannigfaltigen der Anschauungen, als a priori gegeben, ist also der Grund der Identität der Apperzeption selbst, die a priori allem meinem bestimmten Denken vorhergeht. Verbindung liegt aber nicht in den Gegenständen und kann von ihnen nicht etwa durch Wahrnemung entlehnt und in den Verstand dadurch allererst aufgenommen werden, sondern ist allein eine Verrichtung des Verstandes, der selbst nichts weiter ist als das Vermögen, a priori zu verbinden und das Mannigfaltige gegebener Vorstellungen unter Einheit der Apperzeption zu bringen, welcher Grundsatz der oberste im ganzen menschlichen Erkenntnis ist.’

voetnoot1
Richard Kroner also realized this in his famous work: Van Kant bis Hegel, I (1921) p. 85. He defines this antinomy as follows: ‘Wird das Ich als Einheit lediglich im Gegensatze zum Mannigfaltigen (als Verstand im Gegensatze zur Anschauung, als Denken im Gegensatze zum Erkennen) begriffen, so kann es nie synthetisch erkennend werden, die Möglichkeit der Erfahrung ist dahin.’ [If the I is only conceived as a unity in contrast with the manifold - as understanding in contrast with intuition, as thought in contrast with cognition -, it cannot cognize synthetically, then the possibility of experience is gone.]
voetnoot1
op. cit., p. 124, jo, p. 125 note.
voetnoot2
‘Die mannigfaltigen Vorstellungen, die in einer gewissen Anschauung gegeben werden, würden nicht insgesamt meine Vorstellungen sein, wenn sie nicht insgesamt zu einem Selbstbewustztsein gehörten.’
voetnoot3
According to Kant intuitive and at the same time creative thought is only proper to God, as the (hypostatized) intellectus archetypus. Human knowledge is explicitly denied any intuitive character. This is seen in the following passage:
‘Der Verstand wurde oben blosz negativ erklärt: durch ein nicht-sinnliches Erkenntnisvermögen. Nun können wir abhängig von der Sinnlichkeit keiner Anschauung teilhaftig werden. Also ist der Verstand kein Vermögen der Anschauung. Es gibt aber ausser der Anschauung kein andere Art zu erkennen, als durch Begriffe. Also ist die Erkenntnis eines jeden, wenigstens des menschlichen Verstandes, eine Erkenntnis durch Begriffe, nicht intuitiv, sondern diskursiv.’ Op. cit., p. 96. [The understanding was defined negatively in the preceding section: as a non-sensory cognitive faculty. Now we cannot have any intuition apart from sensibility. So the understanding is not a faculty of intuition. Besides our intuition there is no other way to knowledge except by means of concepts. Therefore the knowledge yielded by understanding, at least by human understanding, must be by means of concepts - and so is not intuitive but discursive.]
voetnoot1
op. cit., p. 140: ‘ich (bin) mir meiner selbst in der transszendentalen Synthesis des Mannigfaltigen der Vorstellungen überhaupt, mithin in der synthetischen ursprünglichen Einheit der Apperzeption bewuszt, nicht wie ich mir erscheine, noch wie ich an mir selbst bin, sondern nur dasz ich bin. Diese Vorstellung ist ein Denken, nicht ein Anschauuen.’
voetnoot2
op. cit., p. 141.
voetnoot3
op. cit., the title to § 19, p. 129.
voetnoot4
Compare for instance, p. 322: ‘Das Denken, für sich genommen, ist blosz die logische Funktion, mithin lauter Spontaneität der Verbindung des Mannigfaltigen einer blosz möglichen Anschauung’ etc. [Thought, taken as such, is merely the logical function of synthesis of the manifold of a merely possible intuition etc.]

voetnoot5
‘Denn durch das Ich als einfache Vorstellung (read: concept) ist nichts Mannigfaltiges gegeben.’ [For in the I as a simple representation (- i.e. concept) no manifold content is given.]
voetnoot6
In the first edition der Kr. d.r. V. (W.W. Gr. Wilh. Ernst Ausg. VI, 732) Kant even speaks of the ‘numerische Einheit dieser Apperzeption’ [the numerical unity of this apperception], which is the a priori basis of all concepts.

voetnoot1
Windelband, Gesch. der neueren Phil. II, S. 69 writes that it has been the greatest of Kant's discoveries, ‘dass es neben den logischen noch andere Formen der Verstandestätigkeit gibt, und dass in ihnen der Grund für alle notwendige und allgemeingültige Erkenntnis der Erfahrungswelt zu suchen ist. Diese Formen, welche im Gegensatz zu den reinlogischen die erkenntnistheoretischen genannt werden dürfen, bezeichnete Kant als Kategorien.’ [by the side of the logical forms of intellectual activity there are other forms; in the latter we must seek the foundation of all necessary and universally valid knowledge of the world of experience. We might call these forms epistemological in contradistinction to the purely logical forms. Kant designates them as categories.] But Windelband has not seen that the inter-modal synthesis of meaning was the only thing by which the categories as such could have acquired a more than logical character in Kant's critique of knowledge. But in Kant's cadre of thought it was impossible to conceive this synthesis. There is nowhere any indication that in the categories as such he saw a real inter-modal synthesis of meaning. As we shall show they remain of a merely logical character. But then the distinction between ‘formal’ and ‘transcendental’ forms of thought does not carry us a step further.

voetnoot1
W.W. (Cass.) VIII, 4, p. 401.
voetnoot2
Kr. d.r. V. (Grossh. W.E. Ausg.) p. 104/5. ‘Dieselbe Funktion, welche den verschiedenen Vorstellungen in einem Urteil Einheit gibt, die gibt auch der bloszen Synthesis verschiedener Vorstellungen in einer Anschauung Einheit, welche, allgemein ausgedrückt, der reine Verstandsbegriff heisst. Derselbe Verstand also und zwar durch eben dieselben Handlungen wodurch er in Begriffen, vermittelst der analytischen Einheit die logische Form eines Urteils zu stande brachte, bringt auch vermittelst der synthetischen Einheit des Mannigfaltigen in der Anschauung überhaupt in seine Vorstellungen einen transzendentalen Inhalt, weswegen sie reine Verstandesbegriffe heissen, die a priori auf Objekte gehen, welches die allgemeine Logik nicht leisten kann.’
voetnoot1
‘Diejenige Handlung des Verstandes (aber), durch die das Mannigfaltige gegebener Vorstellungen (sie mögen Anschauungen oder Begriffe sein) unter eine Apperzeption überhaupt gebracht wird, ist die logische Funktion der Urteile. Also ist alles Mannigfaltige, so fern es in einer empirischen Anschauung gegeben ist, in Ansehung einer der logischen Funktionen zu urteilen bestimmt, durch die es nämlich zu einem Bewusztsein überhaupt gebracht wird. Nun sind aber die Kategorien nichts andres als eben diese Funktionen zu urteilen, so fern das Mannigfaltige einer gegebenen Anschauung in Ansehung ihrer bestimmt ist.’
voetnoot2
Kant cannot have meant a real deduction of the categories from the table of the judgments. On this point I agree with Heidegger. Kant himself does not call the table of judgments the ‘origin of the categories’, but only ‘the guide to the discovery of all the concepts of the understanding.’
voetnoot1
Op. cit., p. 159: ‘In der Tat bleibt den reinen Verstandesbegriffen allerdings auch nach Absonderung aller sinnlichen Bedingung eine, aber nur logische Bedeutung der bloszen Einheit der Vorstellungen, denen aber kein Gegenstand, mithin auch keine Bedeutung gegeben wird, die einen Begriff vom Objekt abgeben könnte. So würde z.B. Substanz wenn man die sinnliche Bestimmung der Beharrlichkeit wegliesse, nichts weiter als ein Etwas bedeuten, das als Subjekt (ohne ein Prädikat von etwas anderem zu sein) gedacht werden kann. Aus dieser Vorstellung kann ich nun nichts machen, indem sie mir gar nicht anzeigt, welche Bestimmungen das Ding hat, welches als ein solches erstes Subjekt gelten soll. Also sind die Kategorien ohne Schemata nur Funktionen des Verstandes zu Begriffen, stellen aber keinen Gegenstand vor. Diese Bedeutung kommt ihnen von der Sinnlichkeit, die den Verstand realisiert, indem sie ihn zugleich restringiert.’
voetnoot2
Op. cit., p. 132: ‘da die Kategorien unabhängig von Sinnlichkeit blosz im Verstande entspringen’ etc.
Cf. also § 24, p. 135/6: ‘Die reinen Verstandesbegriffe beziehen sich durch den bloszen Verstand auf Gegenstände der Anschauung überhaupt, unbestimmt ob sie die unsrige oder irgend eine andere doch sinnliche sei, sind aber eben darum blosze Gedankenformen... Die Synthesis oder Verbindung des Mannigfaltigen in denselben bezog sich blosz auf die Einheit der Apperzeption und war dadurch der Grund der Möglichkeit der Erkenntnis a priori, so fern sie auf dem Verstande beruht, und mithin nichts allein transszendental, sondern auch blosz rein intellectual.’ [The pure concepts of the understanding apply to objects of intuition in general, through the understanding alone, no matter whether the intuition is our own or any other, provided only it is sensory, therefore they are mere forms of thought... The synthesis or combination of the manifold in them merely relates to the unity of apperception and because of this it is the ground of the possibility of a priori knowledge in so far as the latter depends on the understanding, and consequently not only transscendental but also purely intellectual.]
voetnoot3
Cf. Ueber die Fortschritte der Metaphysik seit Leibniz und Wolff (W.W. Cass. VIII, 251): ‘Es ist aber wohl zu merken, dass diese Kategorien, oder wie sie sonst heissen, Prädikamente, keine bestimmte Art der Anschauung (wie etwa die uns Menschen allein mögliche) wie Raum und Zeit, welche sinnlich ist, voraussetzen, sondern nur Denkformen sind für den Begriff von einem Gegenstande der Anschauung überhaupt, welcher Art diese auch sei... Denn wir müssen uns immer einen Begriff von einem Gegenstande durch den reinen Verstand machen, von dem wir etwas a priori urteilen wollen, wenn wir auch nachher finden, dass es überschwenglich sei, und ihm keine objektive Realität verschafft werden könne, sodass die Kategorie für sich von den Formen der Sinnlichkeit, Raum und Zeit, nicht abhängig ist.’ [It should, however, be borne in mind that these categories, or ‘predicaments’ as they are also called, do not pre-suppose any definite kind of intuition (as, e.g., that which is only possible in man) such as space and time, which is sensible. But they are mere forms of thought for the concept of an object of intuition as such of whatever nature it may be... For we must always form a concept of an object by means of the pure understanding if we want to predicate something about the object, though later on we find that it is extravagent, and cannot be accorded any objective reality, so that the category as such does not depend on the forms of sensibility, space and time.]
voetnoot1
‘keinen andern Gebrauch zum Erkenntnisse der Dinge (hat), als ihre Anwendung auf Gegenstände der Erfahrung.’

voetnoot2
Not some analogy of it in the psychical or in the logical modus.
voetnoot1
Op. cit., p. 158: ‘das Schema der Qualität’ (enthaltet und macht vorstellig) ‘die Synthesis der Empfindung (Wahrnehmung) mit der Vorstellung der Zeit oder die Erfüllung der Zeit...’
voetnoot2
ibid.
voetnoot1
The reader should remember that the term ‘cosmic time’ is not to be understood in a natural scientific sense, but is used in contrast to the specific scientific concepts of time which refer only to particular modal aspects of temporal experience.
voetnoot1
Kant agrees that the correspondence of the third category of relation to the logical form of a disjunctive judgment is not evident at first sight. But he tries to indicate this correspondence by referring to the fact that the parts of a disjunctive judgment determine each other mutually (when a term of the division is assumed all the others are excluded; and conversely). But this analytical relation of reciprocal determination has nothing to do with interaction in its original physical sense.
voetnoot1
Ibid., p. 107.
voetnoot2
Cf. the proof of the ‘second analogy of experience’. Op. cit. p. 200.
voetnoot1
as ‘Gegenstände’ of sensory intuition.

voetnoot2
Translator's note: The faculty of forming mental images; the word imagination is taken in its primitive sense here.
voetnoot3
‘Die reinen Verstandesbegriffe beziehen sich durch den blossen Verstand auf Gegenstände der Anschauung überhaupt, unbestimmt ob sie die unsrige oder irgend eine andere, doch sinnliche sei, sind aber eben darum blosse Gedankenformen wodurch noch kein bestimmter Gegenstand erkannt wird.’ [The pure concepts of the understanding apply to objects of intuition exclusively through the understanding, and it is immaterial whether the intuition is our own or any other, so long as it is sensory; but they are for this very reason mere forms of thought by means of which no determinate object can be known.]
voetnoot2
op. cit., p. 136: ‘Diese Synthesis des Mannigfaltigen der sinnlichen Anschauung, die apriori möglich und notwendig ist, kann figürlich (synthesis speciosa) genannt werden, zum Unterschiede von derjenigen, welche in Ansehung des Mannigfaltigen einer Anschauung überhaupt in der blossen Kategorie gedacht würde, und Verstandesverbindung (synthesis intellectualis) heisst.’
voetnoot3
The history of the theory of ‘imagination’ can be traced back to ancient and patristic philosophy. St Augustine distinguished a ‘productive’, a ‘reproductive’ and a ‘synthetic’ imagination. In Scholasticism we find explicit mention made of a ‘vis imaginativa’, as a separate faculty of the soul. Nicolaus Cusanus speaks of ‘imaginatio’ or ‘vis phantastica’.
voetnoot1
op. cit., p. 136: ‘Weil in uns aber eine gewisse Form der sinnlichen Anschauung a priori zum Grunde liegt, welche auf der Rezeptivität der Vorstellungsfähigkeit (Sinnlichkeit) beruht, so kann der Verstand als Spontaneität den inneren Sinn durch das Mannigfaltige gegebener Vorstellungen der synthetischen Einheit der Apperzeption gemäss bestimmen und so synthetische Einheit der Apperzeption des Mannigfaltigen der sinnlichen Anschauung apriori denken, als die Bedingung, unter welcher alle Gegenstände unserer (der menschlichen) Anschauung notwendiger Weise stehen müssen, dadurch denn die Kategorien als blosse Gedankenformen objektive Realität, d.i. Anwendung auf Gegenstände, die uns in der Anschauung gegeben werden können, aber nur als Erscheinung bekommen; denn nur von diesen sind wir der Anschauung apriori fähig.’
voetnoot1
Heidegger, op. cit., p. 155/156.
voetnoot1
‘Weil nun der Verstand in uns Menschen selbst kein Vermögen der Anschauungen ist und diese, wenn sie auch in der Sinnlichkeit gegeben wären, doch nicht in sich aufnehmen kann, um gleichsam das Mannigfaltige seiner eigenen Anschauung zu verbinden, so ist seine Synthesis, wenn er für sich allein betrachtet wird, nichts anders als die Einheit der Handlung der er sich als solchen auch ohne Sinnlichkeit bewusst ist, durch die er aber selbst die Sinnlichkeit innerlich in Ansehung des Mannigfaltigen, was der Form ihrer Anschauung nach ihm gegeben werden mag, zu bestimmen vermögend ist. Er also übt unter der Benennung einer transszendentalen Synthesis der Einbildungskraft diejenige Handlung aufs passive Subjekt, dessen Vermögen er ist, aus, wovon wir mit Recht sagen, dass der innere Sinn dadurch affiziert werde.’
voetnoot2
‘Der Verstand findet also in diesem (d.i. dem inneren Sinn) nicht etwa schon eine dergleichen Verbindung des Mannigfaltigen, sondern bringt sie hervor, indem er ihn affiziert.’

voetnoot1
Op. cit., p. 153/154: ‘Nun ist es klar, dass es ein Drittes geben müsse, was einerseits mit der Kategorie, andererseits mit der Erscheinung in Gleichartigkeit’ (Italics are mine) ‘stehen muss und die Anwendung der ersteren auf die letzte möglich macht. Die vermittelnde Vorstellung muss rein (ohne alles Empirische) und doch einerseits intellektuel, andererseits sinnlich sein. Eine solche ist das transszendentale Schema. Der Verstandesbegriff enthält reine synthetische Einheit des Mannigfaltigen überhaupt. Die Zeit als die formale Bedingung des Mannigfaltigen des inneren Sinnes, mithin der Verknüpfung der Vorstellungen, enthält ein Mannigfaltiges a priori in der reinen Anschauung. Nun ist eine transszendentale Zeitbestimmung mit der Kategorie (die die Einheit derselben ausmacht) sofern gleichartig, als sie allgemein ist und auf einer Regel a priori beruht. Sie ist aber andererseits mit der Erscheinung sofern gleichartig, als die Zeit in jeder empirischen Vorstellung des Mannifaltigen enthalten ist. Daher wird eine Anwendung der Kategorie auf Erscheinungen möglich sein vermittelst der transszendentalen Zeitbestimmung, welche als das Schema der Verstandesbegriffe die Subsumtion der letzteren unter die erste vermittelt.’
voetnoot1
‘Die notwendige Verbindung der reinen Begriffe mit den Formen des Anschauens scheint ohne Schwierigkeit bewiesen werden zu können. Sind nicht in dem gemeinsamen Träger des Bewusztseins Denken und Anschauen ursprünglich vereinigt?’
voetnoot2
Only the transcendental logical subject can function as the ‘common subject of consciousness’ in Riehl's Kantian cadre of thought; of course not the ‘empirical ego’ which, according to Kant, is nothing but an individual phenomenon in time and space.
voetnoot3
Der Phil. Krit. I, 480: ‘Zwischen Erkenntnisbegriffen und den Begriffen einer reinlogischen Verknüpfung besteht keinerlei Unterschied des Wesens, sondern nur ein Unterschied der Anwendung. Ihr Gebrauch in rein logischen Sätzen ist analytisch, in Urteilen der Erfahrung synthetisch, in jenen ohne Beziehung auf die allgemeine Form der Anschauung, in diesen mit Beziehung auf diese Form.’
voetnoot1
Although in a quite different sense from what he intended I can agree with Heidegger's pronouncement (op. cit., p. 106) that the chapter on the schematism is ‘the central part of the whole work’. Kant himself writes in 1797: ‘I consider this chapter as one of the most important.’ Handschr. Nachlass W.W. Bnd. V no. 6359. [‘Ich halte dieses Capittel für eines der wichtigsten.’]

voetnoot2
Kr. d.r. V. 1st ed.: ‘Es sind aber drei ursprünglichen Quellen (Tätigkeiten der Vermögen der Seele), die die Bedingungen der Möglichkeit aller Erfahrung enthalten und selbst aus keinem anderen Vermögen des Gemüts abgeleitet werden können, nämlich Sinn, Einbildungskraft und Apperzeption.’ [There are, however, three original sources (activities of the faculties of the soul) that contain the conditions of the possibility of all experience and cannot be derived from any other faculty of the mind, namely sense, imagination and apperception.]
voetnoot1
op. cit. Einleitung, Einteilung der Transszendentalphilosophie: ‘Nur soviel scheint zur Einleitung und Vorerinnerung nötig zu sein, dass es zwei Stämme der menschlichen Erkenntnis gebe, die vielleicht aus einer gemeinschaftlicher aber uns unbekannten’ (Italics are mine) ‘Wurzel entspringen, nämlich Sinnlichkeit und Verstand, durch deren ersteren uns Gegenstände gegeben, durch den zweiten aber gedacht werden.’ [Only so much seems to be necessary to say as an introduction and preface, that there are two stems of human knowledge which perhaps have one common root though unknown to us, viz. sensibility and understanding. Through the former, objects are given us; through the latter they are thought.]
voetnoot2
Heidegger, op. cit., p. 153: ‘Kant ist vor dieser unbekannten Wurzel zurückgewichen. In der zweiten Auflage der Kritik d.r. V. wird die transzendentale Einbildungskraft, so wie sie im leidenschaftlichen Zuge des ersten Entwurfs ans Licht kam, abgedrängt und umgedeutet - zu Gunsten des Verstandes.’
voetnoot3
‘Die Synthesis heisst nur “Einbildungskraft” sofern sie sich auf Anschauung bezieht, ist aber im Grande Verstand’, op. cit. p. 156.
voetnoot1
‘Wird jedoch die transzendentale Einbildungskraft, wie das in der zweiten Auflage geschieht, als eigenes Grundvermögen gestrichen und ihre Funktion dem Verstand als der blossen Spontaneität übertragen, dann schwindet die Möglichkeit reine Sinnlichkeit und reines Denken hinsichtlich ihrer Einheit, in einer endlichen menschlichen Vernunft zu begreifen, ja auch nur zum Problem zu machen.’

voetnoot1
‘das was sie als noch Ungesagtes durch das Gesagte vor Augen legt...’
voetnoot2
‘die Kraft einer vorausleuchtenden Idee die Auslegung (musz) treiben und leiten.’
voetnoot1
viz. in the interpretation according to Heidegger's idea of man's finite existence.
voetnoot2
‘Um freilich dem, was die Worte sagen, dasjenige abzuringen, was sie sagen wollen, muss jede Interpretation notwendig Gewalt gebrauchen’.
voetnoot3
Heidegger op. cit. p. 35: ‘erfahrungsfreies Beibringen der Seinsverfassung des Seienden.’
voetnoot4
Op. cit. p. 35: ‘So verschärft sich die Frage nach der Möglichkeit der apriorischen Synthesis dahin: wie kann ein endliches Wesen, das als solches an das Seiende ausgeliefert und auf die Hinnahme desselben angewiesen ist, vor aller Hinnahme das Seiende erkennen, d.h. anschauen, ohne doch dessen “Schöpfer” zu sein?’

voetnoot1
Op. cit. p. 71: ‘Seiendes wird für ein endliches Wesen nur zugänglich auf dem Grunde eines vorgängig sich zuwendenden Gegenstehen-lassen. Dieses nimmt in vorhinein das möglicherweise begegnende Seiende in den Einheitshorizont einer möglichen Zusammengehörigkeit. Diese a priori einigende Einheit musz dem Begegnenden entgegen vor greifen. Das Begegnende selbst aber ist im vorhinein schon umgriffen durch den in der reinen Anschauung vorgehaltenen Horizont der Zeit. Die vorgreifend einigende Einheit des reinen Verstandes musz sich daher zuvor auch schon mit der reinen Anschauung geeinigt haben. Dieses a priori einige Ganze von reiner Anschauung und reinem Verstand “bildet” den Spielraum des Gegenstehenlassens, in den herein alles Seiende begegnen kann. Im Blick auf dieses Ganze der Transzendenz gilt es zu zeigen, wie, d.h. hier zugleich dasz, reiner Verstand und reine Anschauung a priori auf einander angewiesen sind.’
voetnoot1
Viz. the synthesis of apprehension in sensory intuition, the synthesis of reproduction in imagination, and the synthesis of recognition in concepts.
voetnoot2
op. cit., p. 183: ‘Kant hat durch den Radikalismus, mit dem er bei seiner Grundlegung der Metaphysik zum erstenmal sowohl die Zeit je für sich als auch das “ich denke” je für sich transzendental auslegte, beide in ihre ursprüngliche Selbigkeit zusammengebracht - ohne diese freilich als solche selbst ausdrücklich zu sehen.’
voetnoot3
‘reine Selbstaffektion.’
voetnoot1
‘Vorstellung überhaupt’.
voetnoot2
op. cit., p. 20.
voetnoot3
This way of ‘solving’ the problem was already indicated by Heidegger on page 21 of his book. Referring to Kant's statement: ‘Either of these two (intuition and thought), it is true, is representation, but not yet knowledge,’ Heidegger observes: ‘From this one may infer that between intuition and thought there exists a mutual relation of equal importance so that with the same justification one may say: knowledge is intuiting thought, hence at bottom judgment. But in contrast with this it is necessary to maintain that intuition is the real nature of knowledge and is really the important thing notwithstanding all mutuality in the relation between intuition and thought.’ [‘Hieraus könnte man folgen dass zwischen Anschauen und Denken eine wechselseitige und zwar völlig gleich-gewichtige Bezogenheit bestehe, so dass man auch mit gleichem Recht sagen dürfte: Erkennen ist anschauendes Denken, also im Grunde doch Urteilen. Dem gegenüber muss aber festgehalten werden, dass die Anschauung das eigentliche Wesen der Erkenntnis ausmacht und bei aller Wechselseitigkeit des Bezuges zwischen Anschauen und Denken das eigentliche Gewicht besitzt.’]
Unfortunately Kant's pronouncement quoted above has been taken from his treatise Ueber die Fortschritte der Metaphysik seit Leibniz und Wolff in an answer to the competition instituted by the Königliche Akademie der Wissenschaften of Berlin in 1791. In this Treatise, repeatedly quoted by Heidegger, Kant so sharply opposes the central element of Heidegger's interpretation (the identification of the transcendental self-consciousness with time ‘as pure sensibility’) that I am astonished at Heidegger not even mentioning it. The following quotation may suffice in this connection. (W.W. Cass., Bnd VIII, p. 148/9): ‘Wie es möglich sei, dass ich, der ich denke, mir selber ein Gegenstand (der Anschauung) sein, und so mich von mir selbst unterscheiden könne, ist slechterdings unmöglich zu erklären, obwohl es ein unbezweifeltes Faktum ist; es zeigt aber ein über alle Sinnenanschauung so weit erhabenes Vermögen an,’ (Italics are mine), ‘dass es als der Grund der Möglichkeit eines Verstandes, die gänzliche Absonderung von allem Vieh, dem wir das Vermögen, zu sich selbst Ich zu sagen, nicht Ursache haben beizulegen, zur Folge hat, und in eine Unendlichkeit von selbstgemachten Vorstellungen und Begriffen hinaussieht.’ [How the I who thinks can be an object of intuition to myself and thus distinguish myself from myself, is simply impossible to explain, although it is an undoubted fact; it indicates, however, a faculty which is so much elevated above all sensory intuition (Italics are mine), that, as the basis of the possibility of an understanding, it entails our complete separation from the animals, and looks through an infinity of self-made representations and concepts. For we have no reason to ascribe to animals the power to say I to themselves.]
It is true Kant goes on to say: ‘Er wird dadurch aber nicht eine doppelte Persönlichkeit gemeint, sondern nur Ich, der ich denke und anschaue, ist die Person, das Ich aber des Objektes, was von mir angeschauet wird, ist, gleich andern Gegenständen ausser mir die Sache.’ [By this, however, we do not mean a double personality; but only, the I who thinks and intuits is the person, but the I of the object intuited by me, just like other objects outside of me, is the thing.]
But every attempt to infer an argument for Heidegger's interpretation from this last statement is made impossible by Kant's whole subsequent reasoning. In this he explicitly identifies the ‘I’ in the first sense with the ‘logical I’ and at the end he writes:
‘Das dieses so sei, davon kann uns jede innere, von uns angestellte psychologische Beobachtung zum Beleg und Beispiel dienen, denn es wird dazu erfordert, dass wir den inneren Sinn, zum Teil auch wohl bis zum Grade der Beschwerlichkeit, vermittelst der Aufmerksamkeit affizieren..., um ein Erkenntnis von dem, was uns der innere Sinn darlegt, zuvörderst in der Anschauung unserer Selbst zu haben, welche uns dann uns selbst nur vorstellig macht, wie wir uns erscheinen, indessen dass das logische Ich das Subjekt zwar, wie es an sich ist, im reinen Bewusstsein, nicht als Rezeptivität, sondern reine Spontaneität anzeigt, weiter aber auch keiner Erkenntnis seiner Natur fähig ist.’ (Italics are mine.) [Every internal psychological observation we make, can serve as a proof and an example that things are like this. For this purpose it is required that we affect the inner sense by means of our attention, partly sometimes with great difficulty... in order to have knowledge of that which the inner sense reveals in the first place in the intuition of our own self. In this intuition we are shown as we appear to ourselves, whereas the logical ‘I’ indicates the Subject as it is in itself in the pure consciousness, not as receptivity, but as pure spontaneity. But this logical I is not capable of any further knowledge of its own nature.]
voetnoot1
Heidegger, op. cit., p. 178/9: ‘Wenn die transzendentale Einbildungskraft als das rein bildende Vermögen in sich die Zeit bildet, d.h. entspringen lässt, dann gibt es von der oben ausgesprochenen These: die transzendentale Einbildungskraft ist die ursprüngliche Zeit kein Ausweichen mehr.’ [If the transcendental imagination as the purely formative faculty creates time within itself, i.e. gives rise to time, then the thesis formulated above is inescapable, viz. the transcendental imagination is original time.]

voetnoot1
‘Noch sind Gewissheit und Deutlichkeit zwei Stücke die die Form derselben (i.e. of Kant's investigation) betreffen, als wesentliche Forderungen anzusehen, die man an den Verfasser, der sich an eine so schlüpferige Unternehmung wagt, mit Recht tun kann. Was nun die Gewissheit betrifft, so habe ich mir selbst das Urteil gesprochen: dass es in dieser Art von Betrachtungen auf keine Weise erlaubt sei, zu meinen und dass alles, was darin einer Hypothese nur ähnlich sieht, verbotene Ware sei, die auch nicht für den geringsten Preis feil stehen darf, sondern, sobald sie entdeckt wird, beschlagen werden muss.’
voetnoot1
‘Diese Betrachtung, die etwas tief angelegt ist, hat aber zwei Seiten. Die eine bezieht sich auf die Gegenstände des reinen Verstandes und soll die objektive Gültigkeit seiner Begriffe apriori, dartun und begreiflich machen, eben darum ist sie auch wesentlich zu meinen Zwecken gehörig. Die andere geht darauf aus, den reinen Verstand selbst, nach seiner Möglichkeit und den Erkenntniskräften, auf denen er selbst beruht, mithin ihn in subjektiver Beziehung zu betrachten; und obgleich diese Erörterung in Ansehung meines Hauptzwecks von grosser Wichtigkeit ist, so gehört sie doch nicht wesentlich zu demselben’ (Italics are mine); ‘weil die Hauptfrage immer bleibt: was und wie viel kann Verstand und Vernunft, frei von aller Erfahrung erkennen? und nicht: wie ist das Vermögen zu denken selbst möglich? Da das letztere gleichsam eine Aufsuchung der Ursache zu einer gegebenen Wirkung ist und in sofern etwas einer Hypothese Aehnliches an sich hat (ob es gleich, wie ich bei anderer Gelegenheit zeigen werde, sich in der Tat nicht so verhält), so scheint es, als sei hier der Fall, da ich mir die Erlaubnis nehme, zu meinen, und dem Leser also frei stehen müsse, anders zu meinen. In Betracht dessen muss ich dem Leser mit der Erinnerung zuvorkommen: dass, im Fall meine subjektive Deduktion nicht die ganze Ueberzeugung, die ich erwarte, bei ihm gewirkt hätte, doch die objektive, um die es mir vornehmlich zu tun ist, ihre Stärke bekomme.’
voetnoot1
‘Denn das stehende und bleibende Ich (der reinen Apperzeption) macht das Korrelatum aller unserer Vorstellungen aus, sofern es bloss möglich ist, sich ihrer bewusst zu werden, und alles Bewusstsein gehört eben sowohl zu einer allbefassenden reinen Apperzeption, wie alle sinnliche Anschauung als Vorstellung zu einer reinen innern Anschauung, nämlich der Zeit. Diese Apperzeption ist es nun, welche zu der reinen Einbildungskraft hinzu kommen muss, um ihre Funktion intellektuell zu machen. Denn an sich selbst ist die Synthesis der Einbildungskraft, obgleich a priori ausgeübt, dennoch jederzeit sinnlich, weil sie das Mannigfaltige nur so verbindet, wie es in der Anschauung erscheint, z.B. die Gestallt eines Triangels.’
voetnoot1
W.W. (Grossherzog Wilhelm Ernst Ausg. VI, p. 744.
voetnoot2
This is convincingly shown by our earlier quotation from Kant's: Ueber die Fortschritte der Metaphysik:
‘Es wird dadurch nicht eine doppelte Persönlichkeit gemeint, sondern nur Ich der ich denke und anschaue, ist die Person.’ [No double personality is meant by this, but only the I who thinks and intuits is the person.]
voetnoot3
Cf. our earlier quotation: ‘Synthetische Einheit des Mannigfaltigen als a priori gegeben’ (Italics are mine) ‘ist also der Grund der Identität der Apperzeption selbst.’ [Therefore the synthetic unity of the manifold as an a priori datum is the basis of the identity of the apperception itself.]


Vorige Volgende

Footer navigatie

Logo DBNL Logo DBNL

Over DBNL

  • Wat is DBNL?
  • Over ons
  • Selectie- en editieverantwoording

Voor gebruikers

  • Gebruiksvoorwaarden/Terms of Use
  • Informatie voor rechthebbenden
  • Disclaimer
  • Privacy
  • Toegankelijkheid

Contact

  • Contactformulier
  • Veelgestelde vragen
  • Vacatures
Logo DBNL

Partners

Ga naar kb.nl logo KB
Ga naar taalunie.org logo TaalUnie
Ga naar vlaamse-erfgoedbibliotheken.be logo Vlaamse Erfgoedbibliotheken